•  12
    Review of Joseph Catalano's book Reading Sartre.
  •  92
    Cultivating Virtue
    In Havi Carel & Darian Meacham (eds.), Phenomenology and Naturalism: Examining the Relationship Between Human Experience and Nature, Cambridge University Press. pp. 239-259. 2013.
    Ought you to cultivate your own virtue? Various philosophers have argued that there is something suspect about directing one’s ethical attention towards oneself in this way. These arguments can be divided between those that deem aiming at virtue for its own sake to be narcissistic and those that consider aiming at virtue for the sake of good behaviour to involve a kind of doublethink. Underlying them all is the assumption that epistemic access to one’s own character requires an external point of…Read more
  •  213
    Constancy, Fidelity, and Integrity
    In S. van Hooft, N. Athanassoulis, J. Kawall, J. Oakley & L. van Zyl (eds.), The handbook of virtue ethics, Acumen Publishing. pp. 399-408. 2014.
  •  49
    Virtue and Vice in the Hurt Locker
    Dialogue (37). 2011.
    Much of the critical praise for the film concerns the first of these aims. Bigelow’s use of at least four film crews for every scene affords the sense of being present in the situation, continuously shifting perspective, alert to possible danger. The relative anonymity of the scenery, clearly somewhere in the Middle East but not clearly anywhere in particular, fosters this uneasy sense of immersion in an unfamiliar scenario where the sources of danger are unpredictable. Protracted periods of sil…Read more
  •  85
    Reconstructing Alfie
    The Philosophers' Magazine (47): 61-66. 2009.
    Good stories tend to get told and retold, over and over again, mutating in the process. They adapt to different times and places, taking on and sloughing off embellishments as they are handed on. They persist through a kind of evolution. This is how it has always been and how it must be. Tales cannot survive otherwise. But this does not mean that all mutations are equally acceptable. For critical discussion is part of the environment in which stories survive. So it is not misplaced to criticise …Read more
  •  48
    Green-blooded passion
    The Philosophers' Magazine 43 113-114. 2008.
  •  12
    Character
    The Philosophers' Magazine 50 112-113. 2010.
  •  130
    Habituation and first-person authority
    In Roman Altshuler & Michael Sigrist (eds.), Time and the Philosophy of Action, Routledge. 2016.
    Richard Moran’s theory of first-person authority as the agential authority to make up one’s own mind rests on a form of mind-body dualism that does not allow for habituation as part of normal psychological functioning. We have good intuitive and empirical reason to accept that habituation is central to the normal functioning of desire. There is some empirical support for the idea that habituation plays a parallel role in belief. In particular, at least one form of implicit bias seems better unde…Read more
  •  268
    Webber argues for a new interpretation of Sartrean existentialism. On this reading, Sartre is arguing that each person’s character consists in the projects they choose to pursue and that we are all already aware of this but prefer not to face it. Careful consideration of his existentialist writings shows this to be the unifying theme of his theories of consciousness, freedom, the self, bad faith, personal relationships, existential psychoanalysis, and the possibility of authenticity. Developing …Read more
  •  406
    Liar!
    Analysis 73 (4): 651-659. 2013.
    We have good reason to condemn lying more strongly than misleading and to condemn bullshit assertion less harshly than lying but more harshly than misleading. We each have good reason to mislead rather than make bullshit assertions, but to make bullshit assertions rather than lie. This is because these forms of deception damage credibility in different ways. We can trust the misleader to assert only what they believe to be true. We can trust the bullshitter not to assert what they believe to be …Read more
  •  30
    Cultivating Virtue
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 72 239-259. 2013.
    Ought you to cultivate your own virtue? Various philosophers have argued that there is something suspect about directing one's ethical attention towards oneself in this way. These arguments can be divided between those that deem aiming at virtue for its own sake to be narcissistic and those that consider aiming at virtue for the sake of good behaviour to involve a kind of doublethink. Underlying them all is the assumption that epistemic access to one's own character requires an external point of…Read more
  •  129
    Authenticity
    In Steven Churchill & Jack Reynolds (eds.), Jean-Paul Sartre: Key Concepts, Acumen Publishing. 2013.
    I argue that Sartre's account of the nature and value of authenticity survives Larmore's recent criticism and is preferable to Larmore's alternative account.
  •  295
    Virtue, Character and Situation
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 3 (2): 193-213. 2006.
    Philosophers have recently argued that traditional discussions of virtue and character presuppose an account of behaviour that experimental psychology has shown to be false. Behaviour does not issue from global traits such as prudence, temperance, courage or fairness, they claim, but from local traits such as sailing-in-rough-weather-with-friends-courage and office-party-temperance. The data employed provides evidence for this view only if we understand it in the light of a behaviourist construa…Read more
  •  14
    Reconstructing Alfie
    The Philosophers' Magazine 47 61-66. 2009.
    Now, it don't do to remake a perfectly good film and do a bad job of it. That can rob us of something important. It ain't the sequence of events that makes a good story, see, it's the ideas driving it. And if you ain't got that, what have you got? Know what I mean?
  •  7
    Green-blooded passion (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 43 113-114. 2008.
  •  88
    Knowing One's Own Desires
    In Daniel Dahlstrom, Andreas Elpidorou & Walter Hopp (eds.), Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology: Conceptual and Empirical Approaches, Routledge. pp. 165-179. 2016.
    Do you know your own desires in some way that other people cannot know them? Richard Moran claims that his influential theory of first-person authority over beliefs and intentions can also cover desires. However, his deliberative model can apply to desire only if one already has some other way of knowing one’s own desires. Jean-Paul Sartre’s conception of pure reflection, on the other hand, portrays a direct epistemic access to one’s own desires that can ground fundamental first-person authority…Read more
  •  144
    There Is Something About Inez
    Think (27): 45-56. 2010.
    Hell is other people. This miserable-sounding soundbite, the moment of revelation in Jean- Paul Sartre’s shortest play, must be the most quoted line of twentieth-century philosophy. Not even Jacques Derrida’s claim that ‘there is nothing beyond the text’, fondly cherished in some regions of academia, has anything like the cultural reach of what is often taken to be the quintessential Sartrean slogan. And the analytic tradition hardly abounds in snappy lines: meaning just ain’t in the head, to be…Read more
  •  142
    Motivated aversion: Non-thetic awareness in bad faith
    Sartre Studies International 8 (1): 45-57. 2002.
    Sartre's concept of ‘non-thetic awareness’ must be understood as equivalent to the concept of ‘nonconceptual content’ currently discussed in anglophone epistemology and philosophy of mind, since it could not otherwise play the role in the structure of ‘bad faith’, or self-deception, that Sartre ascribes to it. This understanding of the term makes sense of some otherwise puzzling features of Sartre's early philosophy, and has implications for understanding certain areas of his thought.
  •  54
    Existentialism
    In John Skorupski (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Ethics, Routledge. 2010.
    Since it gained currency at the end of the second world war, the term “existentialism” has mostly been associated with a cultural movement that grew out of the wartime intellectual atmosphere of the Left Bank in Paris and spread through fiction and art as much as philosophy. The theoretical and other writings of Jean-Paul Sartre, Simone de Beauvoir, Albert Camus, and Frantz Fanon in the 1940s and 1950s are usually taken as central to this movement, as are the sculptures of Alberto Giacometti, th…Read more
  •  191
    One of the characteristic features of Sartre’s philosophical writing, especially in Being and Nothingness, is his use of extended narrative vignettes that immediately resound with the reader’s own experience yet are intended to illustrate, perhaps also to support, complex and controversial claims about the structures of conscious experience and the shape of the human condition. Among the best known are his description of Parisian café waiters, who somehow contrive to caricature themselves, and h…Read more
  •  32
    Whatever next?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 20 37-38. 2002.
  •  10
    Review of Joseph S. Catalano, Reading Sartre (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2011 (2). 2011.
  •  164
    Instilling Virtue
    In Alberto Masala & Jonathan Webber (eds.), From Personality to Virtue: Essays on the Philosophy of Character, Oxford University Press Uk. pp. 134-154. 2016.
    Two debates in contemporary philosophical moral psychology have so far been conducted almost entirely in isolation from one another despite their structural similarity. One is the debate over the importance for virtue ethics of the results of situational manipulation experiments in social psychology. The other is the debate over the ethical implications of experiments that reveal gender and race biases in social cognition. In both cases, the ethical problem posed cannot be identified without fir…Read more
  •  323
    Character, Common-Sense, and Expertise
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (1): 89-104. 2007.
    Gilbert Harman has argued that the common-sense characterological psychology employed in virtue ethics is rooted not in unbiased observation of close acquaintances, but rather in the ‘fundamental attribution error’. If this is right, then philosophers cannot rely on their intuitions for insight into characterological psychology, and it might even be that there is no such thing as character. This supports the idea, urged by John Doris and Stephen Stich, that we should rely exclusively on experime…Read more
  •  83
    From Personality to Virtue: Essays on the Philosophy of Character (edited book)
    with Alberto Masala
    Oxford University Press UK. 2016.
    Character plays a central role in our everyday understanding and evaluation of ourselves and one another. It informs the expectations that ground our plans and projects, our moral responses to other people's behaviour and to opportunities we ourselves face, and our political decisions concerning formal education, criminal punishment, and other aspects of social organisation. These philosophical essays clarify this idea of character, analyse its relation with the findings of experimental psycholo…Read more
  •  99
    Green-blooded passion (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 43 (50): 113-114. 2008.
    ‘Of all the difficulties which impede the progress of thought and the formation of well- grounded opinions on life and social arrangements’, wrote John Stuart Mill around 150 years ago, ‘the greatest is now the unspeakable ignorance and inattention of mankind in respect of the influences which form character’. Aristotle is never far in the background of Mill’s moral and political philosophy, a presence weightier than Jeremy Bentham’s in the foreground. That this is often overlooked is not only b…Read more
  •  12
    Motivated Aversion: Non-Thetic Awareness in Bad Faith
    Sartre Studies International 8 45-57. 2002.
  •  134
    Freedom
    In Sebastian Luft & Søren Overgaard (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Phenomenology, Routledge. 2011.
    Human freedom was Jean-Paul Sartre’s central philosophical preoccupation throughout his career. It is hardly surprising, therefore, that the cornerstone of his moral and political thought, Being and Nothingness, contains an extensive and subtle account of the metaphysical freedom that he considered fundamental to the kind of existence that humans have. Although rooted in phenomenology, Sartre’s account of freedom draws very little on analysis of the experience of freedom itself. It is rather bas…Read more