•  28
    Vehicles and Crashes
    Social Theory and Practice 30 (3): 351-370. 2004.
  •  28
    Continuity and Change
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (1): 1-1. 2013.
  •  28
    The Objective(s) of Responsible Brains
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (2): 267-281. 2022.
  •  27
    On the Rights of Non-Persons
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (4). 1980.
    Do non-persons have moral rights? I will suppose this question can best be answered by inquiring whether some animals and/or environmental objects have moral rights, for if any non-persons are possessors of rights, animals and/or environmental objects are the most plausible candidates. As so interpreted, this question has received an extraordinary amount of recent attention from philosophers. Arguments have been offered and defended; rebuttals have appeared in print. Yet, so far as I am aware, n…Read more
  •  26
    Gardner on the Philosophy of Criminal Law
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29 (1): 169-187. 2008.
    Offences and Defences is an outstanding collection of eleven of John Gardner's previously published papers in the philosophy of criminal law. I briefly examine his views on five central issues: his claims about basic responsibility and whether it should be construed as relational; his positions on agent neutrality; his arguments about whether moral and criminal wrongs are typically strict; his thoughts about the structure of defences, and, finally, what his account of rape reveals about the cont…Read more
  •  25
    Criminal Law at the Margins
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (3): 381-393. 2020.
    I describe how our understanding of some of the central principles long held dear by most criminal theorists may have to be interpreted in light of the need to devise lenient responses for low-level offenders. Several of the most plausible suggestions for how to deal with minor infractions force us to take seriously some ideas that many legal philosophers have tended to resist elsewhere. I briefly touch upon four topics: whether informal can substitute for or count against the appropriate state …Read more
  •  25
    The" But-Everyone-Does-That!" Defense
    Public Affairs Quarterly 10 (4): 307-334. 1996.
  •  23
  •  23
    George P. Fletcher, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law New York: Oxford University Press, 1998, xi + 223 pp
  •  21
    The function and structure of the substantive criminal law (review)
    Law and Philosophy 18 (1): 85-104. 1999.
    No Abstract
  •  21
    Reflections on Crime and Culpability seeks to elaborate, extend, and occasionally qualify the insights reached by Larry Alexander and Kim Ferzan in their influential prior collaboration, Crime and Culpability. They deftly explore any number of new issue that all criminal theorists should be encouraged to address. In my essay, I discuss and challenge their positions on omissions as well as on moral ignorance. Their treatment of the latter issue is a clear improvement over that in their earlier bo…Read more
  •  21
  •  19
    Is Fair Opportunity a Comprehensive Theory of Responsibility?
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 1-10. forthcoming.
    I challenge the adequacy of David Brink’s “master principle” of culpability. I allege that it fails to account for the moral relevance of ignorance of wrongdoing. I describe three cases in which I believe that Brink’s theory of normative competence cannot account for the significance of a variable that bears on culpability. In most of this paper I attempt to anticipate and reply to the various responses Brink might offer to my challenge.
  •  19
    Proportionality in Personal Life
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (3): 339-360. 2021.
    Efforts to apply the principle of proportionality to criminal sentences are notoriously problematic. But even though they are daunting, only a few legal philosophers believe we should give up trying to do so. Perhaps we can make progress overcoming some of the many legal difficulties by attending to how the principle is applied in non-legal contexts—that is, in contexts I call personal life. Proportionality, I believe, is an attractive principle in penal sentencing because it is an attractive pr…Read more
  •  18
    Drug legalization
    In Rosamond Rhodes, Leslie Francis & Anita Silvers (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Medical Ethics, Blackwell. 2007.
    The prelims comprise: Introduction 1 Should I Use Drugs? Is the State Justified in Punishing Drug Users? Conclusion References Further Reading.
  •  17
    Ignorance of Law: How to Conceptualize and Maybe Resolve the Issue
    In Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law, Springer Verlag. pp. 315-333. 2019.
    Under what circumstances should ignorance that someone is violating a moral or criminal rule preclude or lessen his moral responsibility and/or penal liability? In this chapter, I first construct a schema or framework for how to think about this issue. Quite a bit of confusion and uncertainty, I am sure, derives from a failure to understand exactly what this question is asking. I next defend some substantive views about how this question should be answered. If my defense is cogent, I conclude th…Read more
  •  17
    Convergent Ends, Divergent Means: A Response to My Critics
    Criminal Justice Ethics 28 (1): 119-134. 2009.
    When writing Overcriminalization, I entertained a fantasy about the reaction my book might produce. I hoped that philosophers would not merely criticize my shortcomings but would join me to produce...
  •  16
    Editorial: Continuity Through Change (review)
    Law and Philosophy 29 (2): 123-125. 2010.
  •  15
    Already Punished Enough
    Philosophical Topics 18 (1): 79-99. 1990.
  •  15
    The Role of Mens Rea in Mediating the Scope of Prohibitions
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 1-14. forthcoming.
    Among the most noteworthy and impressive aspects of A.P. Simester’s monumental Fundamentals of Criminal Law is its pervasive pluralism. Many philosophers of criminal law, I have frequently complained, are excessively monistic on a number of basic questions about which pluralism is the more defensible option. I fear, however, that Simester’s views are sometimes too pluralistic. In particular, he assigns five separate functions to mens rea, and advances the novel claim that “mens rea is not, uniqu…Read more
  •  14
    Require an Act?
    In Antony Duff (ed.), Philosophy and the Criminal Law: Principle and Critique, Cambridge University Press. pp. 60. 1998.
  •  14
    Review of Douglas N. Husak: Drugs and Rights (review)
    Ethics 104 (3): 645-648. 1994.
  •  13
    Introduction
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (3): 337-338. 2021.
  •  12
    Book Review (review)
    Law and Philosophy 42 (3): 311-320. 2023.
  •  12
    Review of mark R. Reiff, Punishment, Compensation, and Law (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (2). 2006.
  •  12
    A Theory of Freedom
    Noûs 26 (3): 400-402. 1992.
  •  11
    Philosophical Analysis and the Limits of the Substantive Criminal Law
    Criminal Justice Ethics 18 (2): 58. 1999.
    George P. Fletcher, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law New York: Oxford University Press, 1998, xi + 223 pp.