•  4
    "Rights, Goods, and Democracy" by Ramon M. Lemos (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (3): 541. 1989.
  • Paternalistic Legislation
    Dissertation, The Ohio State University. 1976.
  •  64
    Killing, letting die and euthanasia
    Journal of Medical Ethics 5 (4): 200-202. 1979.
    Medical ethicists debate whether or not the moral assessment of cases of euthanasia should depend on whether the patient is 'killed' or 'allowed to die'. The usual presupposition is that a clear distinction between killing and letting die can be drawn so that this substantive question is not begged. I contend that the categorisation of cases of instances of killing rather than as instances of letting die depends in part on a prior moral assessment of the case. Hence is it trivially rather than s…Read more
  •  18
    Drug legalization
    In Rosamond Rhodes, Leslie Francis & Anita Silvers (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Medical Ethics, Blackwell. 2007.
    The prelims comprise: Introduction 1 Should I Use Drugs? Is the State Justified in Punishing Drug Users? Conclusion References Further Reading.
  •  85
    Retributivism In Extremis
    Law and Philosophy 32 (1): 3-31. 2013.
    I defend two objections to Tadros’s views on punishment. First, I allege that his criticisms of retributivism are persuasive only against extreme versions that provide no justificatory place for instrumentalist objectives. His attack fails against a version of retributivism that recognizes a chasm between what offenders deserve and the allthings-considered permissibility of treating offenders as they deserve. Second, I critique Tadros’s duty view – his alternative theory of punishment. Inter ali…Read more
  •  3
    Book Review (review)
    Law and Philosophy 29 (1): 101-119. 2009.
  •  157
    Paternalism and autonomy
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1): 27-46. 1981.
  •  97
    Why Punish Attempts at All? Yaffe on 'The Transfer Principle'
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3): 399-410. 2012.
    Gideon Yaffe is to be commended for beginning his exhaustive treatment by asking a surprisingly difficult question: Why punish attempts at all? He addresses this inquiry in the context of defending (what he calls) the transfer principle: “If a particular form of conduct is legitimately criminalized, then the attempt to engage in that form of conduct is also legitimately criminalized.” I begin by expressing a few reservations about the transfer principle itself. But my main point is that we are j…Read more
  •  168
    Negligence, Belief, Blame and Criminal Liability: The Special Case of Forgetting
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 5 (2): 199-218. 2011.
    Commentators seemingly agree about what negligence is—and how it is contrasted from recklessness. They also appear to concur about whether particular examples (both real and hypothetical) portray negligence. I am less confident about each of these matters. I explore the distinction between recklessness and negligence by examining a type of case that has generated a good deal of critical discussion: those in which a defendant forgets that he has created a substantial and unjustifiable risk of har…Read more
  •  96
    The philosophy of criminal law: selected essays
    Oxford University Press. 2010.
    Does criminal liability require an act? -- Motive and criminal liability -- The costs to criminal theory of supposing that intentions are irrelevant to permissibility -- Transferred intent -- The nature and justifiability of nonconsummate offenses -- Strict liability, justice, and proportionality -- The sequential principle of relative culpability -- Willful ignorance, knowledge, and the equal culpability thesis : a study of the significance of the principle of legality -- Rapes without rapists …Read more
  •  44
    Ignorance of Law: A Philosophical Inquiry
    Oxford University Press USA. 2016.
    This book argues that ignorance of law should usually be a complete excuse from criminal liability. It defends this conclusion by invoking two presumptions: first, the content of criminal law should conform to morality; second, mistakes of fact and mistakes of law should be treated symmetrically.
  •  24
    George P. Fletcher, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law New York: Oxford University Press, 1998, xi + 223 pp
  •  5
    Criminal law theory
    In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, Blackwell. 2004.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Need for a Theory of Criminalization The Nature of the Criminal Law Inadequate Theories of Criminalization A Better Approach to Criminalization References Further Reading.
  •  14
    Require an Act?
    In Antony Duff (ed.), Philosophy and the Criminal Law: Principle and Critique, Cambridge University Press. pp. 60. 1998.
  •  28
    On the Rights of Non-Persons
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (4). 1980.
    Do non-persons have moral rights? I will suppose this question can best be answered by inquiring whether some animals and/or environmental objects have moral rights, for if any non-persons are possessors of rights, animals and/or environmental objects are the most plausible candidates. As so interpreted, this question has received an extraordinary amount of recent attention from philosophers. Arguments have been offered and defended; rebuttals have appeared in print. Yet, so far as I am aware, n…Read more
  •  70
    Thirty Years of Law and Philosophy
    Law and Philosophy 30 (2): 141-142. 2011.
  • Transferred Intent
    Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 10 (1): 65-98. 1996.
  •  31
    Benn on privacy and respect for persons
    with Stephen D. Hudson
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57 (4). 1979.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  97
    Intoxication and Culpability
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3): 363-379. 2012.
    I tackle the difficult problem of specifying how voluntary intoxication affects criminal culpability generally and recklessness in particular. I contend that the problem need not be conceptualized as an instance of actio libera in causa, namely the situation in which persons do something at t1 to culpably create the conditions of their own defense at t2. Instead, I argue that we need only consider intoxicated defendants at t2 in order to justify their punishment. In the course of defending my vi…Read more
  •  54
    I examine how deferred-prosecution agreements employed against suspected corporate criminality amount to a form of social engineering that infringes the presumption. I begin with a broad understanding of the presumption itself. Then I offer a brief description of how these agreements function. Finally I address some of the normative issues that must be confronted if legal philosophers who hold retributivist views on punishment and sentencing hope to assess this device. My judgment tends to be fa…Read more
  •  268
    Four points about drug decriminalization
    Criminal Justice Ethics 22 (1): 21-29. 2003.
  •  40
    Drug Proscriptions as Proxy Crimes
    Law and Philosophy 36 (4): 345-366. 2017.
    Our drug policy has been widely deemed a failure because the criminalization of drug use has not succeeded in reducing prevalence rates. I contend that the most promising basis to defend the justifiability of drug offenses is to construe them as proxy crimes: offenses designed to prevent the commission of other, more serious crimes. I make a case that many law enforcement officials use drug proscriptions for this purpose in the real world. When construed as proxy crimes, drug prohibitions are le…Read more
  •  42
    Relativistic justifications
    Law and Philosophy 19 (5). 2000.
  •  73
    [Book review] drugs and rights (review)
    Criminal Justice Ethics 14 (1): 63-72. 1995.
    This important book was the first serious work of philosophy to address the question: Do adults have a moral right to use drugs for recreational purposes? Many critics of the 'war on drugs' denounce law enforcement as counterproductive and ineffective. Douglas Husak argues that the 'war on drugs' violates the moral rights of adults who want to use drugs for pleasure, and that criminal laws against such use are incompatible with moral rights. This is not a polemical tract but a scrupulously argue…Read more