•  53
    Persistence Conditions and Identity
    Metaphysica 20 (1): 73-82. 2019.
    Pluralists believe that there are cases of distinct but spatio-temporally coinciding things. The statue goes, the piece of clay remains: differing persistence conditions, different things. Yet while both are with us, they are obviously in the same place. The argument rests on two assumptions: that statues have their shape essentially and that pieces of clay do not. Only if we make both does the conclusion follow. Here I suggest that while both assumptions are plausible on their face, each may be…Read more
  •  51
    Rescuing ?Begging the question?
    Metaphilosophy 8 (4): 257-271. 1977.
  •  49
    Testimony and "a priori" knowledge
    Philosophical Issues 6 301-310. 1995.
  •  47
    Meaning, translation and interpretation
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (3). 1981.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  36
    Hume's Difficulties with the Self
    Hume Studies 5 (1): 45-54. 1979.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:45. HUME'S DIFFICULTIES WITH THE SELF One of the more baffling and apparently inconclusive parts of the Treatise is the section on personal identity. Hume himself, when he takes a backward glance at it in those notorious passages in the Appendix, singles it out as representing an unresolved problem in his philosophy. It is a matter of fairly general agreement among recent writers on the subject that one of Hume's chief difficulties -…Read more
  •  34
    Hume Variations
    Hume Studies 31 (1): 173-176. 2005.
  •  31
    A logically transparent approach to discourse reporting
    with Corey Washington
    Mind and Language 16 (2). 2001.
    In this essay we develop a theory of discourse reports. The theory provides a common set of structural and interpretive principles that together account for the truth conditions of direct, indirect and mixed reports. A distinguishing feature of our view is the assumption that the complement sentence of a report divides exclusively and exhaustively into regions that characterize the content of the reported utterance and regions that characterize the form of the utterance. This assumption implies …Read more
  •  29
    Hume Variations (review)
    Hume Studies 31 (1): 173-176. 2005.
    It is not uncommon for philosophers to seek the imprimatur of a great predecessor by attempting to show that the truths they proclaim have been perceived by the latter, even if only through a glass darkly. In this slim but rich volume, it is Jerry Fodor’s turn to claim Hume as a philosophical ancestor, both for cognitive science, in general, and for the theory of the mind he has championed for some time, in particular. He writes: “Hume’s Treatise is the foundational document of cognitive science…Read more
  •  29
    Ben L. Mijuskovic, "The Achilles of Rationalist Arguments" (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 16 (4): 477. 1978.
  •  24
    Leading a Double Life: Statues and Pieces of Clay
    Metaphysica 21 (2): 273-277. 2020.
    Some philosophers think that two distinct things can occupy exactly the same region of space, as with a statue and a piece of clay. Others think that the statue and the piece of clay are identical, but not necessarily so. I argue that Alan Gibbard’s well-known story of Goliath and Lumpl does not support either of these claims. Not the first, as there is independent reason to think that it cannot be true. Not the second, because there is no need to invoke the dubiously intelligible notion of cont…Read more
  •  23
    “Dogmatism” and Dogmatism
    Episteme 1-5. forthcoming.
    The so-called paradox of dogmatism has it that it seems that one is both entitled and not entitled to ignore evidence against what one knows. By knowing something, one knows it to be true, and one also knows that there can be no non-misleading evidence against what is true. But to ignore evidence against what one believes – and, surely, one believes what one knows – is to be dogmatic, something one should not be. I argue that there is no genuine paradox here. One's attitude to evidence is govern…Read more
  •  23
    Rearranging the Furniture
    Philosophia 48 (1): 77-81. 2020.
    According to Peter van Inwagen, there are, from the point of view of serious metaphysics, no composites, only simples. Saying that we have built a ship is a misleading way of saying that we have rearranged some simples ship- wise. However, the notion of rearranging simples is problematic, and van Inwagen’s resort to “honorary simples” does not make it less so. Simples can be rearranged only by way of rearranging these, making talk of them not merely a convenient facon de parler, as van Inwagen c…Read more
  •  21
    Frege: Sense and Reference one Hundred Years later (edited book)
    with Petr Kotatko
    Kluwer Academic Publishers. 1995.
    Gottlob Frege's brief article Uber Sinn und Bedeutung (On Sense and Reference) has come to be seen, in the century since its publication in 1892, as one of the seminal texts of analytic philosophy. It, along with the rest of Frege's writings on logic and mathematics, came to mark out a whole new domain of inquiry and to set the agenda for it. This volume bears witness to the continuing importance and influence of that agenda. It contains original papers written by leading Frege scholars for the …Read more
  •  18
    Reply to Forrai: No Reprieve for Gettier “Beliefs”
    Logos and Episteme 10 (3): 327-331. 2019.
    In a recent paper in this journal, Gabor Forrai offers ways to resist my argument that in so-called Gettier cases the belief condition is not, as is commonly assumed, satisfied. He argues that I am mistaken in taking someone's reluctance to assert a proposition he knows follows from a justified belief on finding the latter false as evidence that he does not believe it, as such reluctance may be explained in other ways. While this may be true, I show that it does not affect my central claim which…Read more
  •  16
    The Neo-Fregean Argument
    In Petr Kotatko & John Biro (eds.), Frege: Sense and Reference One Hundred Years Later, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 185--206. 1995.
  •  14
    Editorial Preface
    Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 8 (3): 5-5. 1977.
  •  13
    Ned Block has recently adduced some new arguments to show that “psychologism is true and thus a natural behaviorist analysis of intelligence that is incompatible with psychologism is false”. He introduces a thought experiment in which a machine is programmed to exhibit intelligent-seeming behavior and appeals to our intuition that such a machine is nevertheless not really inteligent; he traces that intuition to the fact that the machine is being thought of as operating with internal processes th…Read more
  •  13
    Two Notes on Composition
    Metaphysica 23 (2): 445-454. 2022.
    If, as some philosophers maintain, there are no composites, we do not have to ask whether, as others hold, composition is identity. Here I argue that both groups are wrong: there are composites, and composition is not identity. I examine one argument for excluding composites from our ontology, based on their alleged causal redundancy. I give reason to think that composites are ineliminable in causal explanations of macroscopic effects. I go on to argue that the relation between composites and th…Read more
  •  12
    While we applaud several aspects of Lilian Bermejo-Luque's novel theory of argumentation and especially welcome its epistemological dimensions, in this discussion we raise doubts about her conception of argumentation, her account of argumentative goodness, and her treatments of the notion of “giving reasons” and of justification.
  •  9
    Book reviews (review)
    with John Dillon, Daniela M. Bailer-Jones, Iseult Honohan, Brian Martine, Christopher Adair-Toteff, Timothy O'Connor, Victor E. Taylor, Richard Rumana, Eileen Brennan, and Julia Tanney
    Humana Mente 5 (1): 111-137. 1997.
    The Morality of Happiness By Julia Annas, Oxford University Press, 1993. Pp. x + 502. ISBN 0–19–507999‐X. £45.00, £13.99. Dimensions of Creativity By Margaret A. Boden MIT Press, 1994. Pp. 242. ISBN 0–262–02368–7. £24.95. Thomas Hobbes and the Science of Moral Virtue By David Boonin‐Vail, Cambridge University Press, 1994. Pp. 219. ISBN 0–521–46209–6. £37.50. Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes By Quentin Skinner, Cambridge University Press, 1996. Pp. 477. ISBN 0–521–55436–5. £35.00. …Read more
  •  7
    Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes (edited book)
    Oxford University Press USA. 2002.
    This collection of previously unpublished essays on Spinoza provides a sample of new and interesting research on the philosopher. The essays investigate such themes as Spinoza's monism, the nature of the individual, the relation between mind and body, and his place in 17th century philosophy.
  •  7
    Mind, Brain, and Function: Essays in the Philosophy of Mind (edited book)
    with Robert W. Shahan
    Oklahoma University Press. 1982.
    With the discovery in 1995 of the first planet orbiting another star, we know that planets are not unique to our own Solar System. For centuries, humanity has wondered whether we are alone in the Universe. We are now finally one step closer to knowing the answer. The quest for exoplanets is an exciting one, because it holds the possibility that one day we might find life elsewhere in the Universe, born in the light of another sun. Written from the perspective of one of the pioneers of this scien…Read more
  •  6
    Consideraciones en torno a la pragma-dialéctica
    Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 24 (2): 193-201. 2014.
  •  2
    Hume's new science of the mind
    In David Fate Norton & Jacqueline Taylor (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Hume, Cambridge University Press. 1993.
  •  1
    Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes
    Philosophical Quarterly 54 (217): 627-628. 2004.
  • Frege: Sense and Reference One Hundred Years Later
    with Petr Kotatko
    Studia Logica 61 (3): 433-439. 1998.
  • Conventionality In Speech Acts
    Southwest Philosophical Studies 3. 1978.
    The question of the relative importance and precise delineation of conventional and non-conventional elements in speech acts was regarded as central in their analysis by Austin himself, and has continued to exercise subsequent writers on the subject.