•  30
    Representation and covariation
    In Stuart Silvers (ed.), ReRepresentation, Kluwer Academic Publishers. 1989.
  •  3
    Interpretational semantics
    In Steven P. Stitch & Ted A. Warfield (eds.), mental representation: a reader, Blackwell. 1994.
    This is a condensed version of the material in chapters 8-10 in Meaning and Mental Representation (MIT, 1989). It is an explanation and defence of a theory of content for the mind considered as a symbolic computational process. It is a view i abandoned shortly thereafter when I abandoned symbolic computatioalism as a viable theory of cognition.
  •  275
    Innate modules vs innate learning biases
    with Denise D. Cummins
    Cognitive Processing. 2005.
    Proponents of the dominant paradigm in evolutionary psychology argue that a viable evolutionary cognitive psychology requires that specific cognitive capacities be heritable and “quasi-independent” from other heritable traits, and that these requirements are best satisfied by innate cognitive modules. We argue here that neither of these are required in order to describe and explain how evolution shaped the mind
  •  27
    Causes and representation
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1): 76-76. 1980.
  •  622
    Explanation and Subsumption
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978. 1978.
    The thesis that subsumption is sufficient for explanation is dying out, but the thesis that it is necessary is alive and well. It is difficult to attack this thesis: non-subsumptive counter-examples are declared incomplete, or mere promissory notes. No theory, it is thought, can be explanatory unless it resorts to subsumption at some point. In this paper I attack this thesis by describing a theory that (1) would explain every event it could describe, (2) does not explain by subsumption, and (3) …Read more
  •  39
    The Philosophical Problem of Truth-Of
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1). 1975.
    There is a certain view abroad in the land concerning the philosophical problems raised by Tarskian semantics. This view has it that a Tarskian theory of truth in a language accomplishes nothing of interest beyond the definition of truth in terms of satisfaction, and, further, that what is missing — the only thing that would yield a solution to the philosophical problem of truth when added to Tarskian semantics — is a reduction of satisfaction to a non-semantic relation. It seems to me that this…Read more
  •  279
    Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology (edited book)
    with André Ariew and Mark Perlman
    Oxford University Press. 2002.
    But what are functions? Here, 15 leading scholars of philosophy of psychology and philosophy of biology present new essays on functions.
  •  405
    Systematicity
    Journal of Philosophy 93 (12): 591-614. 1996.
  •  36
    The language faculty and the interpretation of linguistics
    with Robert M. Harnish
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1): 18-19. 1980.
  •  338
    Neo-teleology
    In Andre Ariew, Robert Cummins & Mark Perlman (eds.), Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology, Oxford University Press. 2002.
    Neo-teleology is the two part thesis that, e.g., (i) we have hearts because of what hearts are for: Hearts are for blood circulation, not the production of a pulse, so hearts are there--animals have them--because their function is to circulate the blood, and (ii) that (i) is explained by natural selection: traits spread through populations because of their functions. This paper attacks this popular doctrine. The presence of a biological trait or structure is not explained by appeal to its functi…Read more
  •  1
    Dispositions, states and causes
    Analysis 34 (6): 194-204. 1974.
  •  52
    Haugeland on representation and intentionality
    In Hugh Clapin (ed.), Philosophy of Mental Representation, Oxford University Press. 2002.
    Haugeland doesn’t have what I would call a theory of mental representation. Indeed, it isn’t clear that he believes there is such a thing. But he does have a theory of intentionality and a correlative theory of objectivity, and it is this material that I will be discussing in what follows. It will facilitate the discussion that follows to have at hand some distinctions and accompanying terminology I introduced in Representations, Targets and Attitudes (Cummins, 1996; RTA hereafter). Couching the…Read more
  •  73
    Connectionism, computation, and cognition
    with Georg Schwarz
    In Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 60--73. 1991.
  •  33
    Traits have not evolved to function the way they do because of a past advantage
    with Robert Cummins and Martin Roth
    In Francisco José Ayala & Robert Arp (eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 72--88. 2010.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Functional Attribution: Meeting the Explanatory Constraint Functional Attribution: Normativity Postscript: Counterpoint Notes References.
  •  116
    Why it doesn’t matter to metaphysics what Mary learns
    Philosophical Studies 167 (3): 541-555. 2014.
    The Knowledge Argument of Frank Jackson has not persuaded physicalists, but their replies have not dispelled the intuition that someone raised in a black and white environment gains genuinely new knowledge when she sees colors for the first time. In what follows, we propose an explanation of this particular kind of knowledge gain that displays it as genuinely new, but orthogonal to both physicalism and phenomenology. We argue that Mary’s case is an instance of a common phenomenon in which someth…Read more
  •  100
    Representation and indication
    In Hugh Clapin (ed.), Representation in Mind, Elsevier. pp. 21--40. 2004.
    This paper is about two kinds of mental content and how they are related. We are going to call them representation and indication. We will begin with a rough characterization of each. The differences, and why they matter, will, hopefully, become clearer as the paper proceeds
  •  105
    Meaning and Content in Cognitive Science
    In Richard Schantz (ed.), Prospects for Meaning, Walter De Gruyter. pp. 365-382. 2012.
    What are the prospects for a cognitive science of meaning? As stated, we think this question is ill posed, for it invites the conflation of several importantly different semantic concepts. In this paper, we want to distinguish the sort of meaning that is an explanandum for cognitive science—something we are going to call meaning—from the sort of meaning that is an explanans in cognitive science—something we are not going to call meaning at all, but rather content. What we are going to call …Read more
  •  17
    Could Have Done Otherwise
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 60 (4): 411. 1979.
  •  61
    Epistemology and the Cartesian circle
    Theoria 41 (3): 112-124. 1975.
  •  71
    Two troublesome claims about qualities in Locke's essay
    Philosophical Review 84 (3): 401-418. 1975.
    In book two, Chapter eight of the essay, Locke claims that primary qualities, Unlike secondary qualities, Are really in objects and are resemblances of our ideas. The idioms of containment and of resemblance are explained as formulations of what jonathan bennett calls the analytic thesis and the causal thesis. It is argued that locke was concerned to distinguish primary qualities from what he calls secondary qualities because he thought the latter were not really qualities at all but mere powers…Read more
  •  60
    Analysis and subsumption in the behaviorism of Hull
    Philosophy of Science 50 (March): 96-111. 1983.
    The background hypothesis of this essay is that psychological phenomena are typically explained, not by subsuming them under psychological laws, but by functional analysis. Causal subsumption is an appropriate strategy for explaining changes of state, but not for explaining capacities, and it is capacities that are the central explananda of psychology. The contrast between functional analysis and causal subsumption is illustrated, and the background hypothesis supported, by a critical reassessme…Read more
  •  499
    States, causes, and the law of inertia
    Philosophical Studies 29 (1). 1976.
    I argue that Galileo regarded unaccelerated motion as requiring cause to sustain in. In an inclined plane experiment, the cause ceases when the incline ceases. When the incline ceases, what ceases is acceleration, not motion. Hence, unaccelerated motion requires no cause to sustain it.
  •  94
    The Modularity of Mind
    with Jerry Fodor
    Philosophical Review 94 (1): 101. 1983.
  •  54
    On an Argument for Truth-Functionality
    with Dale Gottlieb
    American Philosophical Quarterly 9 (3). 1972.
    Quine argued that any context allowing substitution of logical equivalents and coextensive terms is truth functional. We argue that Quine's proof for this claim is flawed.
  •  467
    Inexplicit information
    In Myles Brand & Robert M. Harnish (eds.), The Representation of Knowledge and Belief, University of Arizona Press. 1986.
    A discussion of a number of ways that information can be present in a computer program without being explicitly represented.
  •  19
    Berkeley
    Philosophical Review 88 (2): 299. 1979.
  •  153
    Conceptual role semantics and the explanatory role of content
    Philosophical Studies 65 (1-2): 103-127. 1992.
    I've tried to argue that there is more to representational content than CRS can acknowledge. CRS is attractive, I think, because of its rejection of atomism, and because it is a plausible theory of targets. But those are philosopher's concerns. Someone interested in building a person needs to understand representation, because, as AI researchers have urged for some time, good representation is the secret of good performance. I have just gestured in the direction I think a viable theory of repres…Read more