Annandale-on-Hudson, New York, United States of America
Areas of Interest
Philosophy of Mind
  •  18
    Review of Stephen Davies, Themes in the Philosophy of Music (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (1). 2006.
  •  64
    Art as Language: Wittgenstein, Meaning, and Aesthetic Theory
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (4): 388-389. 1995.
  •  15
    Aristotle's Mimesis and Abstract Art
    Philosophy 59 (229): 365-371. 1984.
    Does non-representational art itself constitute a refutation of any theory of art based upon mimesis or imitation? Our intuitions regarding this question seem to support an affirmative answer: it appears impossible to account for abstract and non-representational art in terms of imitation, because, to put the problem simply, if nothing is copied in a work of art then there can be nothing essentially imitative about it. The very notion of abstract imitative art seems self-contradictory.
  •  32
    Wittgenstein's aesthetics
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2007.
  •  41
    Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor, by Ted Cohen (review)
    Mind 119 (476): 1145-1151. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  3
    Book reviews (review)
    British Journal of Aesthetics 30 (3): 287-288. 1990.
  • No Title available: New Books (review)
    Philosophy 67 (259): 123-125. 1992.
  •  12
    Philosophy and Literature: A Book of Essays
    British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (4): 428-431. 2006.
  • Jenefer Robinson, ed., Music and Meaning (review)
    Philosophy in Review 19 52-55. 1999.
  •  12
    War of the Worldviews
    with Denis Dutton
    Philosophy and Literature 26 (1). 2002.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 26.1 (2002) iii-iv [Access article in PDF] Editorial War of the Worldviews With this issue, PHILOSOPHY AND LITERATURE enters its second quarter century. For many of the past twenty-five years it has enjoyed the sponsorship of Whitman College and the extraordinarily capable coeditorship of Patrick Henry. Bard College now assumes sponsorship, and the journal will be edited jointly by us, with Pat Henry ascendi…Read more
  •  27
    Introduction: On the Ground of Ethical Criticism
    Philosophy and Literature 39 (1A). 2015.
    One can characterize the relation between philosophy and literature in a number of interestingly different ways: literature provides examples that put flesh on the bones of philosophical ideas; literature shows what philosophy says; literature serves philosophy by displaying the complexity of circumstance that philosophy may oversimplify; literature captures a kind of content that is not amenable to propositional encapsulation; literature offers a portal into an imaginative world and a special k…Read more
  •  38
    Wittgenstein, Music and the Philosophy of Culture
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 21 23-40. 2014.
    Wittgenstein’s scattered remarks on music, when brought together and then related to his similarly scattered remarks on culture, show a deep and abiding concern with music as a repository and conveyer of meaning in human life. Yet the conception of meaning at work in these remarks is not of a kind that is amenable to brief or concise articulation. This paper explores that conception, considering in turn the relational networks within which musical meaning emerges, what he calls a discernible “ki…Read more
  •  19
    Goldman, Alan H. Philosophy and the Novel. Oxford University Press, 2013, 209 pp., $53.40 cloth (review)
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (3): 332-335. 2014.
  •  44
    Understanding happiness
    Mind 93 (372): 589-591. 1984.
  •  32
    Self-Expression
    British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (1): 107-109. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  74
    Art and the unsay able: Langer's tractarian aesthetics
    British Journal of Aesthetics 24 (4): 325-340. 1984.
  •  16
    Music and Imagination
    Philosophy 61 (238). 1986.
    When we inquire into the nature of works of art we can see at a glance that there is a good deal of evidence against aesthetic idealism, the view that artworks are, in the final analysis, imaginary objects in the minds of their creators. We believe, for instance, that the National Gallery not only contingently but in some sense necessarily weighs more than merely the sum of the empty building, the people in it, and the assorted fixtures. This sum must also include the weight of canvases, the oil…Read more
  •  172
    What, after all, is a work of art?
    British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2): 206-209. 2002.
  •  23
    Editor's Note
    Philosophy and Literature 36 (1). 2012.
  •  3
    Book review (review)
    British Journal of Aesthetics 30 (4): 376-378. 1990.
  •  312
    On philosophy as therapy: Wittgenstein, Cavell, and autobiographical writing
    Philosophy and Literature 27 (1): 196-210. 2003.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 27.1 (2003) 196-210 [Access article in PDF] On Philosophy as Therapy:Wittgenstein, Cavell, and Autobiographical Writing Garry Hagberg IN HIS LATER PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS Wittgenstein was exquisitely sensitive to the misleading implications housed within the formulations of philosophical questions. The question with which he opened the Blue Book, "What is the meaning of a word?," the question "What is thinkin…Read more