•  3
    Foreword
    Criminal Justice Ethics 22 (1): 21-21. 2003.
  •  17
    Postscript
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 7 (2). 1973.
    John Kleinig; Postscript 1, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 7, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 177–178, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9752.1973.tb00479.
  •  17
    From Social Justice to Criminal Justice: Poverty and the Administration of Criminal Law (edited book)
    with William C. Heffernan
    Oxford University Press USA. 2000.
    The economically deprived come into contact with the criminal court system in disproportionate number. This collection of original, interactive essays, written from a variety of ideological perspectives, explores some of the more troubling questions and ethical dilemmas inherent in this situation. The contributors, including well-known legal and political philosophers Philip Pettit, George Fletcher, and Jeremy Waldron, examine issues such as heightened vulnerability, indigent representation, and…Read more
  •  48
    The Paternalistic Principle
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (2): 315-327. 2016.
    In this paper, I critique one aspect of Simester and von Hirsch’s, Crimes, Harms, and Wrongs—their recognition of harm and offence principles, but failure to construct a paternalistic principle, despite their willingness to countenance some small measure of criminal paternalism. Construction of such a principle would have clarified the problems of as well as the limits to criminalising paternalism.
  •  5
    Ethics and Criminal Justice: An Introduction (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2008.
    This textbook looks at the main ethical questions that confront the criminal justice system - legislature, law enforcement, courts, and corrections - and those who work within that system, especially police officers, prosecutors, defence lawyers, judges, juries, and prison officers. John Kleinig sets the issues in the context of a liberal democratic society and its ethical and legislative underpinnings, and illustrates them with a wide and international range of real-life case studies. Topics co…Read more
  •  4
    Linguistics in Philosophy (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 18 (n/a): 262-264. 1969.
    J L Austin has left a firm imprint on much contemporary philosophy. Not surprisingly, however, his published papers and lectures have provoked strongly contrasting responses, some seeing in them the refinement of certain philosophical techniques and the introduction of new standards of care, others the final degeneration of linguistic philosophy into verbal hair-splitting. Whatever the response, his writings were bound to attract the attention of formal linguists, and the last decade has seen a …Read more
  •  13
    The Ethics of Consent
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 8 (n/a): 91-118. 1982.
    We would not be far wide of the mark if we suggested that the prevailing social ideology is structured round the presumption that interpersonal and political relationships ought to be, and for the most part are, based on the mutual consent of the parties involved. Liberal democratic theory has secured for consent a crucial role in the justification of political obligation and authority. In law, the maximvolenti non fit injuria,to the one who consents no wrong is done, constitutes a defence in ca…Read more
  •  5
    Contents
    In [Book review] valuing life, Princeton University Press. 1993.
  •  9
    Introduction
    In [Book review] valuing life, Princeton University Press. 1993.
  •  5
    Six. Human life
    In [Book review] valuing life, Princeton University Press. pp. 115-163. 1993.
  •  2
    Acknowledgments
    In [Book review] valuing life, Princeton University Press. 1993.
  •  44
    Principles of neutrality in education
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 8 (2). 1976.
  •  29
    Mercy and Justice
    Philosophy 44 (170). 1969.
  •  6
    Editor's introduction
    Criminal Justice Ethics 10 (1): 11-11. 1991.
  •  27
    Paternalism and Personal Identity
    Jahrbuch für Wissenschaft Und Ethik 14 (1): 93-106. 2009.
  •  62
    Disenfranchising Felons
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (3): 217-239. 2005.
  •  1
    WALKER, N.: "Punishment, Danger and Stigma: The Morality of Criminal Justice" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (n/a): 193. 1982.
  •  7
    Notes
    In [Book review] valuing life, Princeton University Press. pp. 229-256. 1993.
  •  8
    The Limits of Consent
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 7 (2): 63-65. 1992.
  •  75
    Loyalty
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  123
  •  6
    Bibliography
    In [Book review] valuing life, Princeton University Press. pp. 257-276. 1993.
  • AHERN, M. B.: The Problem of Evil (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (n/a): 45. 1972.
  •  21
    R. S. Peters on punishment
    British Journal of Educational Studies 20 (3). 1972.
    No abstract
  •  14
    The conscientious advocate and client perjury
    Criminal Justice Ethics 5 (2): 3-15. 1986.
    No abstract
  •  47
    Freewill and Determinism (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 18 (n/a): 260-262. 1969.
    The distinctiveness of this addition to the already vast literature on the freewill controversy is shown by its subtitle. Professor Franklin believes that what is ultimately at stake in the debate is not conceptual clarification, but our fundamental values and conception of man. Paraphrasing Hare: to justify a position completely, we have to give a complete specification of the way of life of which it is a part.
  •  120
    Gun control: The issues
    Criminal Justice Ethics 20 (1): 17-18. 2001.
    No abstract