•  14
    The conscientious advocate and client perjury
    Criminal Justice Ethics 5 (2): 3-15. 1986.
    No abstract
  • AHERN, M. B.: The Problem of Evil (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (n/a): 45. 1972.
  •  20
    R. S. Peters on punishment
    British Journal of Educational Studies 20 (3). 1972.
    No abstract
  •  120
    Gun control: The issues
    Criminal Justice Ethics 20 (1): 17-18. 2001.
    No abstract
  •  46
    Freewill and Determinism (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 18 (n/a): 260-262. 1969.
    The distinctiveness of this addition to the already vast literature on the freewill controversy is shown by its subtitle. Professor Franklin believes that what is ultimately at stake in the debate is not conceptual clarification, but our fundamental values and conception of man. Paraphrasing Hare: to justify a position completely, we have to give a complete specification of the way of life of which it is a part.
  •  12
    T0. The Concept of Desert
    In Louis P. Pojman & Owen McLeod (eds.), What Do We Deserve?: A Reader on Justice and Desert, Oxford University Press. pp. 84. 1999.
  •  9
    Ethical Challenges for Intervening in Drug Use: Policy, Research, and Treatment Issues
    with Stanley Einstein
    Criminal Justice Ethics 26 (2): 72. 2007.
  •  2
    Paternalism
    Law and Philosophy 4 (1): 115-119. 1985.
  • Megan's Law: Community Notification of the Release of Sex Offenders
    with William C. Hefferman and Timothy Stevens
    Criminal Justice Ethics 14 (2): 3-4. 1995.
  •  31
    The fourth chapter of mill's utilitarianism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48 (2). 1970.
    The arguments of the fourth chapter of 'utilitarianism' have been given considerable attention in recent years. the present article suggests that the major (and most controversial) part of the chapter is concerned not so much with the proof as with the kind of proof to which the principle of utility is susceptible. it is argued that the chapter progresses in an orderly manner to outline the kinds of considerations which would be necessary to show (a) that happiness is desirable as an end; (b) th…Read more
  •  92
    Crime and the Concept of Harm
    American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (1). 1978.
  •  71
    Mill, children, and rights
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 8 (1). 1976.
  •  5
    Seven. Towards a morality of life
    In Valuing Life, Princeton University Press. pp. 164-189. 1991.
  •  3
    Index of names
    In Valuing Life, Princeton University Press. pp. 277-280. 1991.
  •  22
    Penalty enhancement for hate crimes
    Criminal Justice Ethics 11 (2): 3-6. 1992.
  •  117
    Good samaritanism
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 5 (4): 382-407. 1976.
  •  91
    Passmore's philosophy of teaching
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 18 (1). 1986.
  •  14
    Editorial introduction
    Criminal Justice Ethics 26 (1): 3-4. 2007.
    No abstract
  •  7
    Editorial introduction
    Criminal Justice Ethics 17 (1): 42-42. 1998.
  •  19
    Three. Organismic life
    In Valuing Life, Princeton University Press. pp. 46-69. 1991.
  •  15
    Compulsory schooling
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 15 (2). 1981.
    John Kleinig; Compulsory Schooling, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 15, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 191–203, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9752.1981.
  •  37
    This volume explores at length the contours of an important and troubling virtue -- its cognates, contrasts, and perversions; its strengths and weaknesses; its awkward relations with universal morality; its oppositional form and limits; as well as the ways in which it functions invarious associative connections, such as friendship and familial relations, organizations and professions.
  •  180
    The Ethics of Policing (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1996.
    This book is the most systematic, comprehensive and philosophically sophisticated discussion of police ethics yet published. It offers an in-depth analysis of the ethical values that police, as servants of the community, should uphold as they go about their task. The book considers the foundations and purpose of police authority in broad terms but also tackles specific problems such as accountability, the use of force, deceptive stratagems used to gain information or trap the criminally intentio…Read more
  •  48
    Butler in a cool hour
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 7 (4): 399-411. 1969.
  •  113
    Legitimate and Illegitimate Uses of Police Force
    Criminal Justice Ethics 33 (2): 83-103. 2014.
    Utilizing a contractualist framework for understanding the basis and limits for the use of force by police, this article offers five limiting principles—respect for status as moral agents, proportionality, minimum force necessary, ends likely to be accomplished, and appropriate motivation—and then discusses uses of force that violate or risk violating those principles. These include, but are not limited to, unseemly invasions, strip searches, perp walks, handcuffing practices, post-chase apprehe…Read more
  •  79
    The Ethical Perils of Knowledge Acquisition
    Criminal Justice Ethics 28 (2): 201-222. 2009.
    At first blush, there would seem to be few ethical problems with knowledge acquisition in a law enforcement context. For that context is one of public safety and criminal justice, both worthy ends,...
  •  24
    Handled with Discretion: Ethical Issues in Police Decision Making (edited book)
    Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 1996.
    Criticisms of how police exercise their authority are neither new nor uncommon. Police officers have considerable power, and they often must draw on that power in complex and pressing circumstances. This collection of essays by fifteen leading specialists in ethics and criminal justice examines the nature of police discretion and its many varieties. The essays explore the kinds of judgment calls police officers frequently must make: When should they get involved? Whom should they watch? What con…Read more