•  99
    On desires and practical reasons
    Acta Analytica 19 (32): 5-18. 2004.
    A common and plausible assumption about the relation between desires and practical reasons—namely, that if øing is an optimal way (or even just a way) for a person, P, to satisfy one of his or her desires, then P has a (normative) reason to ø. This paper discusses that assumption. Although it does not deny that desires are a source of practical reasons, it shows that in some situations, rare though not impossible, P can lack a reason to ø despite having a desire that he or she could satisfy opti…Read more
  •  786
    Hutcheson's Theological Objection to Egoism
    Journal of Scottish Philosophy 14 (1): 101-123. 2016.
    Francis Hutcheson's objections to psychological egoism usually appeal to experience or introspection. However, at least one of them is theological: It includes premises of a religious kind, such as that God rewards the virtuous. This objection invites interpretive and philosophical questions, some of which may seem to highlight errors or shortcomings on Hutcheson's part. Also, to answer the questions is to point out important features of Hutcheson's objection and its intellectual context. And no…Read more
  • Cultural Relativism, Universalism, and the Burden of Proof
    Millennium: Journal of International Studies 27 (2): 275-97. 1998.
  •  908
    In this paper, I challenge a familiar argument -- a composite of arguments in the literature -- for the view that “Why be moral?” is a pseudo-question. I do so by refuting a component of that argument, a component that is not only crucial to the argument but important in its own right. That component concerns the status of moral reasons in replies to “Why be moral?”; consequently, this paper concerns reasons and rationality no less than it concerns morality. The work I devote to those topics sho…Read more
  •  251
    Desires, Reasons, and Reasons to be Moral
    American Philosophical Quarterly 41 (4): 287-298. 2004.
    Opening sentences: "This paper concerns an argument which, in this author's experience, often comes up in discussions of 'Why be moral?' Although initially tempting, the argument is in error. The error warrants attention not only because it spoils the argument but because it connects to a second error which is easy to make. Both errors concern the relation between desires and (normative) practical reasons."
  •  287
    Wollaston, William
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Wiley. 2022.
    This is a brief reference article on William Wollaston's moral theory, including some influential objections to it.
  •  387
    Spectres of False Divinity: Hume’s Moral Atheism (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 50 (2): 297-298. 2012.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Spectres of False Divinity: Hume’s Moral AtheismJohn J. TilleyThomas Holden. Spectres of False Divinity: Hume’s Moral Atheism. Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press, 2010. Pp. xvi + 246. Cloth, $50.00.Thomas Holden argues that a key element of David Hume’s irreligious agenda is his case for moral atheism. According to Holden, Hume defends (conclusively, Hume believes) not merely weak moral atheism, according to which t…Read more
  •  1737
    Is "Why Be Moral?" A Pseudo-Question?: Hospers and Thornton on the Amoralist's Challenge
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (4): 549-66. 2006.
    Many arguments have been advanced for the view that "Why be moral?" is a pseudo-question. In this paper I address one of the most widely known and influential of them, one that comes from John Hospers and J. C. Thornton. I do so partly because, strangely, an important phase of that argument has escaped close attention. It warrants such attention because, firstly, not only is it important to the argument in which it appears, it is important in wider respects. For instance, if it is sound it has w…Read more
  •  37027
    Cultural Relativism
    Human Rights Quarterly 22 (2). 2000.
    In this paper I refute the chief arguments for cultural relativism, meaning the moral (not the descriptive) theory that goes by that name. In doing this I walk some oft-trodden paths, but I also break new ones. For instance, I take unusual pains to produce an adequate formulation of cultural relativism, and I distinguish that thesis from the relativism of present-day anthropologists, with which it is often conflated. In addition, I address not one or two, but eleven arguments for cultural relat…Read more
  •  5464
    Hedonism
    In Ruth Chadwick (ed.), Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics, 2nd ed., vol. 2, Academic Press. pp. 566-73. 2012.
    This article covers four types of hedonism: ancient hedonism; ethical hedonism; axiological hedonism; and psychological hedonism. It concentrates on the latter two types, both by clarifying them and by discussing arguments in their behalf. It closes with a few words about the relevance of those positions to applied ethics.