•  497
    Do belief reports report beliefs?
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (3): 215-241. 1997.
    The traditional puzzles about belief reports puzzles rest on a certain seemingly innocuous assumption, that 'that'-clauses specify belief contents. The main theories of belief reports also rest on this "Specification Assumption", that for a belief report of the form 'A believes that p' to be true,' the proposition that p must be among the things A believes. I use Kripke's Paderewski case to call the Specification Assumption into question. Giving up that assumption offers prospects for an intuiti…Read more
  •  21
    When to ask, "what if everyone did that?"
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37 (4): 464-481. 1977.
  •  55
    More on self-deception: Reply to Hellman
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (June): 611-614. 1985.
  •  117
    Russell was right (almost)
    Synthese 54 (2). 1983.
    I defend russell's main views on names and descriptions against recent objections. Ordinary names are not logically proper names (or rigid designators) but really are disguised descriptions (of the form "the bearer of "n""). And russell's theory of descriptions really works. The common objections to russell all suffer from a confusion of use with meaning. However, Russell was wrong to think that there are or need to be any logically proper names (at least for particulars). That is because, So I …Read more
  •  14
    "Change in View: Principles of Reasoning" by Gilbert Harman (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 761. 1988.
  •  83
    What Does it Take to Refer?
    In Ernie Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press. pp. 516--554. 2005.
    This article makes a number of points about reference, both speaker reference and linguistic reference. The bottom line is simple: reference ain't easy — at least not nearly as easy as commonly supposed. Much of what speakers do that passes for reference is really something else, and much of what passes for linguistic reference is really nothing more than speaker reference. Referring is one of the basic things we do with words, and it would be a good idea to understand what that involves and req…Read more
  •  79
    Review of Francois Recanati, Literal meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2). 2007.
  •  30
  •  144
    The Lure of Linguistification
    In Carlo Penco & Filippo Domaneschi (eds.), What Is Said and What Is Not: The Semantics/pragmatics Interface, Chicago University Press. 2013.
    Think of linguistification by analogy with personification: attributing linguistic properties to nonlinguistic phenomena. For my purposes, it also includes attributing nonlinguistic properties to linguistic items, i.e., treating nonlinguistic properties as linguistic. Linguistification is widespread. It has reached epidemic proportions. It needs to be eradicated. That’s important because the process of communication is not simply a matter of one person putting a thought into words and another de…Read more
  •  207
    How performatives really work: A reply to Searle (review)
    with Robert M. Harnish
    Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (1). 1992.
  •  49
    Analytic social philosophy—basic concepts
    Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 5 (2). 1975.
  •  20
    Talk about wine
    In Fritz Allhoff (ed.), Wine and Philosophy, Blackwell. pp. 95--110. 2008.
  •  7
    Failed Reference and Feigned Reference
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 25 (1): 359-374. 1985.
    Nothing can be said about a nonexistent object, but something can be said about the act of (unsuccessfully) attempting to refer to one or, as in fiction, of pretending to refer to one. Unsuccessful reference, whether by expressions or by speakers, can be explained straightforwardly within the context of the theory of speech acts and communication. As for fiction, there is nothing special semantically, as to either meaning or reference, about its language. And fictional discourse is just a distin…Read more
  •  7
    Exit-existentialism
    Wadsworth Pub. Co.. 1973.
  •  84
    Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts
    with Warren Ingber and Robert M. Harnish
    Philosophical Review 91 (1): 134. 1982.
  •  142
    Even though it’s based on a bad argument, there’s something to Strawson’s dictum. He might have likened ‘referring expression’ to phrases like ‘eating utensil’ and ‘dining room’: just as utensils don’t eat and dining rooms don’t dine, so, he might have argued, expressions don’t refer. Actually, that wasn’t his argument, though it does make you wonder. Rather, Strawson exploited the fact that almost any referring expression, whether an indexical, demonstrative, proper name, or definite descriptio…Read more
  •  18
    Subject and name index
    In Rita Finkbeiner, Jörg Meibauer & Petra B. Schumacher (eds.), What is a Context?: Linguistic Approaches and Challenges, John Benjamins. pp. 196--251. 2012.
  •  77
    Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong
    Philosophical Review 109 (4): 627. 2000.
    As the dust jacket proclaims, “this is surely Fodor’s most irritating book in years …. It should exasperate philosophers, linguists, cognitive psychologists, and cognitive neuroscientists alike.” Yes, Fodor is an equal-opportunity annoyer. He sees no job for conceptual analysts, no hope for lexical semanticists, and no need for prototype theorists. When it comes to shedding light on concepts, these luminaries have delivered nothing but moonshine. Fodor aims to remedy things, and not just with sn…Read more
  •  183
    What's in a name
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (4). 1981.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  150
    Meaning and Communication
    In Gillian Russell & Delia Graff Fara (eds.), Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Language, Routledge. pp. 79--90. 2011.
    Words mean things, speakers mean things in using words, and these need not be the same. For example, if you say to someone who has just finished eating a super giant burrito at the Taqueria Guadalajara, “You are what you eat,” you probably do not mean that the person is a super giant burrito. So we need to distinguish the meaning of a linguistic expression – a word, phrase, or sentence – from what a person means in using it. To simplify matters, let us pretend that an utterance is always of a se…Read more
  •  26
    Replies to My Critics
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 13 (2): 217-249. 2013.
    I thank my critics for time, thought, and effort put into their commentaries. Since obviously I can’t respond to everything, I will try to address what strike me as the most important questions they ask and objections they raise. I think I have decent answers to some questions and decent responses to some objections, in other cases it seems enough to clarify the relevant view, and in still others I need to modify the view in question. One complication, which I won’t elaborate on, is that the vie…Read more
  •  498
    Frege's and Russell's views are obviously different, but because of certain superficial similarities in how they handle certain famous puzzles about proper names, they are often assimilated. Where proper names are concerned, both Frege and Russell are often described together as "descriptivists." But their views are fundamentally different. To see that, let's look at the puzzle of names without bearers, as it arises in the context of Mill's purely referential theory of proper names, aka the 'Fid…Read more
  •  119
    Terms of agreement
    Ethics 105 (3): 604-612. 1995.
    Can two promises add up to an agreement? Not according to Margaret Gilbert. 1 She has forcefully challenged the orthodox view that an agreement is an exchange of promises. She works through an intricate series of examples of promise-exchanges and argues that none qualifies as an agreement. Assuming that she has not overlooked any plausible candidates, she concludes that agreements are essentially different. It seems, however, that her examples are all exchanges of promises only in an attenuated …Read more
  •  219
    Knowledge in and out of context
    In Joseph Campbell (ed.), Knowledge and Skepticism, Mit Press. pp. 105--36. 2010.
    In this chapter, the author offers another explanation of the variation in contents, which is explained by contextualism as being related to a variation in standards. The author’s explanation posits that the contents of knowledge attributions are invariant. The variation lies in what knowledge attributions we are willing to make or accept. Although not easy to acknowledge, what contextualism counts as knowledge varies with the context in which it is attributed. A new rival to contextualism, know…Read more
  •  109
    Refraining, Omitting, and Negative Acts
    In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action, Wiley-blackwell. 2010.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Ways of Failing to Do Something Refraining Omitting Negative Acts: Inaction as Action? References.
  •  5
    Burge’s New Thought Experiment: Back to the Drawing Room
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (2): 88-97. 1988.