•  186
    Engineering the mind (review of Dretske 1995, Naturalizing the Mind) (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (2): 459-468. 1997.
    No contemporary philosopher has tried harder to demystify the mind than Fred Dretske. But how to demystify it without eviscerating it? Can consciousness be explained? Many philosophers think that no matter how detailed and systematic our knowledge becomes of how the brain works and how it subserves mental functions, there will always remain an "explanatory gap." Call it a brute fact or call it a mystery, trying to explain consciousness, they think, is as futile as trying to explain why there is …Read more
  •  219
    Perspectives on possibilities: contextualism, relativism, or what?
    In Andy Egan & Brian Weatherson (eds.), Epistemic Modality, Oxford University Press. 2009.
    Epistemic possibilities are relative to bodies of information, or perspectives. To claim that something is epistemically possible is typically to claim that it is possible relative one’s own current perspective. We generally do this by using bare, unqualified epistemic possibility (EP) sentences, ones that don’t mention our perspective. The fact that epistemic possibilities are relative to perspectives suggests that these bare EP sentences fall short of fully expressing propositions, contrary to…Read more
  •  194
    I'd like to present a puzzle about belief reports that's been nagging at me for several years. I've subjected many friends and audiences to various abortive attempts at solving it. Now it's time to get it off my chest and let others try their hand at it.<1>
  •  120
    Standardization vs. conventionalization
    Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (6). 1995.
  •  487
    Do belief reports report beliefs?
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (3): 215-241. 1997.
    The traditional puzzles about belief reports puzzles rest on a certain seemingly innocuous assumption, that 'that'-clauses specify belief contents. The main theories of belief reports also rest on this "Specification Assumption", that for a belief report of the form 'A believes that p' to be true,' the proposition that p must be among the things A believes. I use Kripke's Paderewski case to call the Specification Assumption into question. Giving up that assumption offers prospects for an intuiti…Read more
  •  21
    When to ask, "what if everyone did that?"
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37 (4): 464-481. 1977.
  •  53
    More on self-deception: Reply to Hellman
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (June): 611-614. 1985.
  •  162
    Saying, meaning, and implicating
    In Keith Allan & Kasia Jaszczolt (eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, Cambridge University Press. 2012.
  •  152
    What Does it Take to Refer?
    In Ernest Lepore & Barry Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press. pp. 516--554. 2006.
    This article makes a number of points about reference, both speaker reference and linguistic reference. The bottom line is simple: reference ain't easy — at least not nearly as easy as commonly supposed. Much of what speakers do that passes for reference is really something else, and much of what passes for linguistic reference is really nothing more than speaker reference. Referring is one of the basic things we do with words, and it would be a good idea to understand what that involves and req…Read more
  •  79
    Review of Francois Recanati, Literal meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2). 2007.
  •  117
    Russell was right (almost)
    Synthese 54 (2). 1983.
    I defend russell's main views on names and descriptions against recent objections. Ordinary names are not logically proper names (or rigid designators) but really are disguised descriptions (of the form "the bearer of "n""). And russell's theory of descriptions really works. The common objections to russell all suffer from a confusion of use with meaning. However, Russell was wrong to think that there are or need to be any logically proper names (at least for particulars). That is because, So I …Read more
  •  13
    "Change in View: Principles of Reasoning" by Gilbert Harman (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 761. 1988.
  •  144
    Think of linguistification by analogy with personification: attributing linguistic properties to nonlinguistic phenomena. For my purposes, it also includes attributing nonlinguistic properties to linguistic items, i.e., treating nonlinguistic properties as linguistic. Linguistification is widespread. It has reached epidemic proportions. It needs to be eradicated. That’s important because the process of communication is not simply a matter of one person putting a thought into words and another de…Read more
  •  206
    How performatives really work: A reply to Searle (review)
    with Robert M. Harnish
    Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (1). 1992.
  •  30
  •  20
    Talk about wine
    In Fritz Allhoff (ed.), Wine and Philosophy, Blackwell. pp. 95--110. 2008.
  •  6
    Failed Reference and Feigned Reference
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 25 (1): 359-374. 1985.
    Nothing can be said about a nonexistent object, but something can be said about the act of (unsuccessfully) attempting to refer to one or, as in fiction, of pretending to refer to one. Unsuccessful reference, whether by expressions or by speakers, can be explained straightforwardly within the context of the theory of speech acts and communication. As for fiction, there is nothing special semantically, as to either meaning or reference, about its language. And fictional discourse is just a distin…Read more
  •  49
    Analytic social philosophy—basic concepts
    Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 5 (2). 1975.
  •  7
    Exit-existentialism
    Wadsworth Pub. Co.. 1973.
  •  80
    Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts
    with Warren Ingber and Robert M. Harnish
    Philosophical Review 91 (1): 134. 1982.
  •  142
    Even though it’s based on a bad argument, there’s something to Strawson’s dictum. He might have likened ‘referring expression’ to phrases like ‘eating utensil’ and ‘dining room’: just as utensils don’t eat and dining rooms don’t dine, so, he might have argued, expressions don’t refer. Actually, that wasn’t his argument, though it does make you wonder. Rather, Strawson exploited the fact that almost any referring expression, whether an indexical, demonstrative, proper name, or definite descriptio…Read more
  •  158
    Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong
    Philosophical Review 109 (4): 627. 2000.
    As the dust jacket proclaims, “this is surely Fodor’s most irritating book in years …. It should exasperate philosophers, linguists, cognitive psychologists, and cognitive neuroscientists alike.” Yes, Fodor is an equal-opportunity annoyer. He sees no job for conceptual analysts, no hope for lexical semanticists, and no need for prototype theorists. When it comes to shedding light on concepts, these luminaries have delivered nothing but moonshine. Fodor aims to remedy things, and not just with sn…Read more
  •  179
    What's in a name
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (4). 1981.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  150
    Meaning and Communication
    In G. Russell & D. G. Fara (eds.), Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Routledge. pp. 79--90. 2012.
    Words mean things, speakers mean things in using words, and these need not be the same. For example, if you say to someone who has just finished eating a super giant burrito at the Taqueria Guadalajara, “You are what you eat,” you probably do not mean that the person is a super giant burrito. So we need to distinguish the meaning of a linguistic expression – a word, phrase, or sentence – from what a person means in using it. To simplify matters, let us pretend that an utterance is always of a se…Read more
  •  18
    Subject and name index
    In Rita Finkbeiner, Jörg Meibauer & Petra Schumacher (eds.), What is a Context?: Linguistic Approaches and Challenges, John Benjamins. pp. 196--251. 2012.
  •  119
    Terms of agreement
    Ethics 105 (3): 604-612. 1995.
    Can two promises add up to an agreement? Not according to Margaret Gilbert. 1 She has forcefully challenged the orthodox view that an agreement is an exchange of promises. She works through an intricate series of examples of promise-exchanges and argues that none qualifies as an agreement. Assuming that she has not overlooked any plausible candidates, she concludes that agreements are essentially different. It seems, however, that her examples are all exchanges of promises only in an attenuated …Read more