•  71
    Literal Meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2): 487-492. 2007.
  •  68
    Picoeconomics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4): 981-983. 1995.
    There is a simple view of motivation on which desires are like pain-killers; they come in different strengths, and their strength determines their efficacy. That is, the stronger a desire the greater its motivational force and, when two desires conflict, the stronger one “wins out” over the weaker. This view makes it puzzling how anyone could ever exhibit “strength of will” and act on the weaker desire, even when it is a desire for something more highly valued than what is more strongly desired.…Read more
  •  64
    Spreading the Word (review)
    Philosophical Review 96 (1): 120. 1987.
  •  64
    Literal Meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2): 487-492. 2007.
  •  53
    More on self-deception: Reply to Hellman
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (June): 611-614. 1985.
  •  53
    There is a problem when these people list all these flavours and aromas they think they have detected. It then gets on to the label of the bottle and what you are looking at appears to be a recipe for fruit salad. – Hugh Johnson.
  •  51
    Critical notice
    In Brian P. McLaughlin & Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception, University of California Press. 1988.
    As philosophical topics go, self-deception has something for everyone. It raises basic questions about the nature of belief and the relation of belief to thought, desire, and the will. It provokes further questions on such topics as reasoning, attention, self-knowledge, the unity of the self, intentional action, motivation, self-esteem, psychic defenses, the unconscious, personal character, and interpersonal relations. There are two basic questions about self-deception itself, which each take a …Read more
  •  49
    Analytic social philosophy—basic concepts
    Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 5 (2). 1975.
  •  46
    Minimal Semantics
    Philosophical Review 116 (2): 303-306. 2007.
  •  41
    Relevant questions
    with Robert M. Harnish
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4): 711. 1987.
  •  40
    Ramachandran vs. Russell
    Analysis 54 (3). 1994.
  •  38
    Katz as Katz can
    with Robert M. Harnish
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (3): 168-171. 1982.
  •  35
    Index of Names: Volume 22
    with F. Ackerman, G. Anscombe, H. Aristar-Dry, C. L. Baker, and S. Bayer
    Linguistics and Philosophy 22 (6): 681-687. 1999.
  •  30
  •  27
    The Main Bone of Contention
    European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 3 (2): 55-58. 2007.
    I enumerate the main disagreements between Devitt and me, and then elucidate the most fundamental one. It concerns what it takes to refer to something. Devitt takes a liberal view on this, according to which a speaker’s having a certain object in mind and intending to refer to it puts the hearer in a position to form singular thoughts about it. There is no requirement that the hearer have any independent access to the object. My view is more restrictive, not allowing “reference borrowing” of the…Read more
  •  27
    The Excluded Middle: Semantic Minimalism without Minimal Propositions
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2): 435-442. 2007.
    Herman Cappelen and Ernie Lepore’s book is ultimately a defense of their self-styled Semantic Minimalism, but it’s mainly a protracted assault on semantic Contextualism, both moderate and radical. They argue at length that Moderate Contextualism leads inevitably to Radical Contextualism and at greater length that Radical Contextualism is misguided. Supposing that “[Radical Contextualism] is the logical consequence of denying Semantic Minimalism”, they think they have given an indirect argument f…Read more
  •  26
    Replies to My Critics
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 13 (2): 217-249. 2013.
    I thank my critics for time, thought, and effort put into their commentaries. Since obviously I can’t respond to everything, I will try to address what strike me as the most important questions they ask and objections they raise. I think I have decent answers to some questions and decent responses to some objections, in other cases it seems enough to clarify the relevant view, and in still others I need to modify the view in question. One complication, which I won’t elaborate on, is that the vie…Read more
  •  25
    A criterion for toothache?
    Philosophical Studies 19 (4). 1968.
  •  23
    Self-deception unmasked (review)
    Philosophical Psychology 15 (2): 203-206. 2002.
    Al Mele has been as persistent as anyone in his pursuit of self-deception. He has taken it on in a series of papers over the past twenty years and at various places in previous books. The present book brings together his main ideas on the subject, and readers unfamiliar with its puzzles or Mele's approach to it will learn a lot. The cognoscenti will not only have their memories refreshed but will be treated to much that is new, including recent experimental work that Mele marshals in support of …Read more
  •  23
    Acknowledgment
    with Pauline Jacobson, Shalom Lappin, Martin Stokhof, Daniel Buring, Peter Lasersohn, Thomas Ede, Paul Dekker Beth Levin Zimmermann, Julie Sedivy, and Ben Russell
    Linguistics and Philosophy 28 781-782. 2005.
    Acknowledgment of peer reviewers
  •  22
    Change in View: Principles of Reasoning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 761-764. 1988.
  •  22
    Representation, Meaning, and Thought
    Philosophical Review 103 (3): 544. 1994.
  •  21
    When to ask, "what if everyone did that?"
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37 (4): 464-481. 1977.