•  1245
    On the Moral Epistemology of Ideal Observer Theories
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 (3): 359-374. 2006.
    : In this paper I attempt to defuse a set of epistemic worries commonly raised against ideal observer theories. The worries arise because of the omniscience often attributed to ideal observers – how can we, as finite humans, ever have access to the moral judgements or reactions of omniscient beings? I argue that many of the same concerns arise with respect to other moral theories (and that these concerns do not in fact reveal genuine flaws in any of these theories), and further, that we can a…Read more
  •  360
    Russ Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 59 (1): 204-205. 2005.
    A short review of Russ Shafer-Landau's Moral Realism: A Defence.
  •  765
    Grounded knowledge, place and epistemic virtue
    Ethics, Place and Environment 8 (3). 2005.
    A response to Christopher Preston's book "Grounding Knowledge" (2003). I first argue that Preston’s work strongly suggests that epistemologists would do well to re-examine and pay greater attention to ‘knowledge how’. Second, I briefly consider several of Preston’s proposals (concerning the importance of place to our cognitive lives) through the lens of contemporary virtue epistemology and suggest how Preston’s work might inform and shape theorizing in this area. Finally, I turn to a set of pot…Read more
  •  445
    Rethinking Greed
    In Allen Thompson Jeremy Bendik-Keymer (ed.), Human Adaptation to Climate Change: Human Virtues of the Future, The Mit Press. pp. 223-39. 2012.
    In this paper I attempt to clarify the nature of the vice of greed, focusing on what can be called “modest greed”. Agents who are modestly greedy do not long for material goods or wealth with intense desires. Rather, they have quite modest desires, but ones whose satisfaction they pursue excessively relative to other goods. Greed - including modest greed - emerges as a particularly troubling and problematic vice.
  •  1669
    Virtue theory, ideal observers, and the supererogatory
    Philosophical Studies 146 (2): 179-96. 2008.
    I argue that recent virtue theories (including those of Hursthouse, Slote, and Swanton) face important initial difficulties in accommodating the supererogatory. In particular, I consider several potential characterizations of the supererogatory modeled upon these familiar virtue theories (and their accounts of rightness) and argue that they fail to provide an adequate account of supererogation. In the second half of the paper I sketch an alternative virtue-based characterization of supererogatio…Read more
  •  2662
    Reverence for Life as a Viable Environmental Virtue
    Environmental Ethics 25 (4): 339-358. 2003.
    There have been several recent defenses of biocentric individualism, the position that all living beings have at least some moral standing, simply insofar as they are alive. I develop a virtue-based version of biocentric individualism, focusing on a virtue of reverence for life. In so doing, I attempt to show that such a virtuebased approach allows us to avoid common objections to biocentric individualism, based on its supposed impracticability (or, on the other hand, its emptiness).
  •  877
    On Complacency
    American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (4): 343-55. 2006.
    This paper begins by drawing attention to inadequacies in common characterizations of the vice of complacency. An alternative account is presented that avoids these flaws. The distinctive nature of complacency is then clarified by contrasting it with related vices, including apathy, resignation, akrasia, excessive pride, and hypocrisy.
  •  288
    Is (merely) stalking sentient animals morally wrong?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 17 (2). 2000.
    Such activities as tracking, watching, and photographing animals are frequently presented as morally superior alternatives to hunting, but could they themselves be morally problematic? In this paper I argue that, despite certain differences from the stalking of humans, a strong case can be made for the prima facie wrongness of stalking sentient animals. The chief harm of stalking is the fear and altered patterns of behavior which it forces upon its victims.
  •  31
    Dale Jamieson, Ethics and the Environment (review)
    Environmental Ethics 31 (3): 333-336. 2009.
    A short book review of Dale Jamieson's "Ethics and the Environment"
  •  2803
    The experience machine and mental state theories of well-being
    Journal of Value Inquiry 33 (3): 381-387. 1999.
    It is argued that Nozick's experience machine thought experiment does not pose a particular difficulty for mental state theories of well-being. While the example shows that we value many things beyond our mental states, this simply reflects the fact that we value more than our own well-being. Nor is a mental state theorist forced to make the dubious claim that we maintain these other values simply as a means to desirable mental states. Valuing more than our mental states is compatible with maint…Read more
  •  752
    Promising and supererogation
    Philosophia 32 (1-4): 389-398. 2005.
    A paradox involving promises to perform supererogatory actions is developed. Several attempts to resolve the problem, focusing in particular on changing our understanding of supererogatory actions, are explored. It is concluded that none of the proposed solutions are viable; the problem lies in promises with certain contents, not in our understanding of supererogation.
  •  1767
    Moral Realism and Arbitrariness
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (1): 109-129. 2005.
    In this paper I argue (i) that choosing to abide by realist moral norms would be as arbitrary as choosing to abide by the mere preferences of a God (a difficulty akin to the Euthyphro dilemma raised for divine command theorists); in both cases we would lack reason to prefer these standards to alternative codes of conduct. I further develop this general line of thought by arguing in particular (ii) that we would lack any noncircular justification to concern ourselves with any such realist normati…Read more
  •  183
    Harry G. Frankfurt, The Reasons of Love (review)
    Philosophy in Review 24 (5): 322-324. 2004.