•  1586
    Autonomy, agency, and the value of enduring beliefs
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (1). 2010.
    My central thesis is that philosophers considering questions of epistemic value ought to devote greater attention to the enduring nature of beliefs. I begin by arguing that a commonly drawn analogy between beliefs and actions is flawed in important respects, and that a better, more fruitful analogue for belief would be desire, or a similarly enduring state of an agent. With this in hand, I argue that treating beliefs as enduring, constitutive states of agents allows us to capture the importance …Read more
  •  299
    Ronald Sandler and Philip Cafaro, Environmental Virtue Ethics (review)
    Environmental Ethics 28 (4): 429-32. 2006.
    A short review of "Environmental Virtue Ethics" (2005), a collection edited by Ronald Sandler and Philip Cafaro.
  •  29
    Alan Thomas, Value and Context: The Nature of Moral and Political Knowledge (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (9). 2007.
    This is, surprisingly enough, a review of Alan Thomas' "Value and Context: The Nature of Moral and Political Knowledge". A very nice book. More details in the review itself.
  •  1238
    Other–regarding epistemic virtues
    Ratio 15 (3). 2002.
    Epistemologists often assume that an agent’s epistemic goal is simply to acquire as much knowledge as possible for herself. Drawing on an analogy with ethics and other practices, I argue that being situated in an epistemic community introduces a range of epistemic virtues (and goals) which fall outside of those typically recognized by both individualistic and social epistemologists. Candidate virtues include such traits as honesty, integrity (including an unwillingness to misuse one’s status as …Read more
  •  210
    John Cottingham, On the Meaning of Life (review)
    Philosophy in Review 24 (1): 22-24. 2004.
  •  1577
    Friendship and epistemic norms
    Philosophical Studies 165 (2): 349-370. 2013.
    Simon Keller and Sarah Stroud have both argued that the demands of being a good friend can conflict with the demands of standard epistemic norms. Intuitively, good friends will tend to seek favorable interpretations of their friends’ behaviors, interpretations that they would not apply to strangers; as such they seem prone to form unjustified beliefs. I argue that there is no such clash of norms. In particular, I argue that friendship does not require us to form beliefs about our friends in the …Read more
  •  199
    Thomas L. Carson, Value and the Good Life (review)
    Philosophy in Review 22 (4): 260-262. 2002.
  •  301
    Peter Heinegg, ed., Mortalism: Readings on the Meaning of Life (review)
    Philosophy in Review 24 (1): 22. 2004.
  •  863
    Moral response-dependent metaethical theories characterize moral properties in terms of the reactions of certain classes of individuals. Nick Zangwill has argued that such theories are flawed: they are unable to accommodate the motive of duty. That is, they are unable to provide a suitable reason for anyone to perform morally right actions simply because they are morally right. I argue that Zangwill ignores significant differences between various approvals, and various individuals, and that mora…Read more
  •  221
    Inner Diversity
    Philosophy in the Contemporary World 8 (2): 27-35. 2001.
    I propose a modified virtue ethics, grounded in an analogy between ecosystems and human personalities. I suggest that we understand ourselves as possessing changing systems of inter-related sub personalities with different virtues, and view our characters as flexible and evolving.
  •  125
    The handbook of virtue ethics (edited book)
    Acumen Publishing. 2014.
    Virtue ethics has emerged as a distinct field within moral theory - whether as an alternative account of right action or as a conception of normativity which departs entirely from the obligatoriness of morality - and has proved itself invaluable to many aspects of contemporary applied ethics. Virtue ethics now flourishes in philosophy, sociology and theology and its applications extend to law, politics and bioethics. 'The handbook of virtue ethics' brings together leading international scholars …Read more
  •  1355
    Self-regarding supererogatory actions
    Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (3). 2003.
    Many philosophers, in discussing supererogation, maintain that supererogatory actions must be done for the benefit of others. In this paper I argue that there can be instances of self-regarding supererogatory actions. That is, there are cases in which the primary (or sole) intended beneficiary of a supererogatory action is the agent herself, and she need not be acting out of a concern for morality or moral rules. In such cases the agent still acts suitably 'beyond the call of duty', and in a mor…Read more
  •  652
    On promising to supererogate: A response to Heyd
    Philosophia 34 (2): 153-156. 2006.
    In my “Promising and Supererogation” I argue that one cannot fulfill promises to perform supererogatory actions (such as “I hereby promise to perform one supererogatory action every month”). In a response to my paper, David Heyd argues that there is an alternative solution to the problem I raise. While I agree with much that Heyd says about the examples he discusses, his proposed solution involves a crucial alteration of the problem; his proposed solution does not solve the problem I present.