Boston University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1985
Victoria, British Columbia, Canada
  •  23
    E. Lepore : "Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (n/a): 249. 1988.
  •  47
    The Ancient and Modern System of the Arts
    British Journal of Aesthetics 55 (1): 1-17. 2015.
    Paul Oskar Kristeller famously argued that the modern ‘ system of the arts ’ did not emerge until the mid-eighteenth century, in the work of Charles Batteux. On this view, the modern conception of the fine arts had no parallel in the ancient world, the middle-ages or the modern period prior to Batteux. This paper argues that Kristeller was wrong. The ancient conception of the imitative arts completely overlaps with Batteux’s fine arts : poetry, painting, music, sculpture, and dance. Writers from…Read more
  •  75
    Some members of the Vienna Circle argued for a coherence theory of truth. Their coherentism is immune to standard objections. Most versions of coherentism are unable to show why a sentence cannot be true even though it fails to cohere with a system of beliefs. That is, it seems that truth may transcend what we can be warranted in believing. If so, truth cannot consist in coherence with a system of beliefs. The Vienna Circle's coherentists held, first, that sentences are warranted by coherence wi…Read more
  •  55
    A Defence of the Coherence Theory of Truth
    Journal of Philosophical Research 26 89-101. 2001.
    Recent critics of the coherence theory of truth (notably Ralph Walker) have alleged that the theory is incoherent, since its defence presupposes the correctness of the contrary correspondence theory of truth. Coherentists must specify the system of propositions with which true propositons cohere (the specified system). Generally, coherentists claim that the specified system is a system composed of propositions believed by a community. Critics of coherentism maintain that the coherentist’s assert…Read more
  •  20
    Review of noël Carroll, Art in Three Dimensions (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2010 (12). 2010.
  •  11
    Aesthetics (edited book)
    Routledge. 2005.
    This four volume set brings together both classic and contemporary writings to provide a comprehensive collection of the most important essays on the subject. All of the various artistic genres are addressed, with sections on film, dance and architecture as well as music, literature and the visual arts. With a new introduction by the editor to guide the reader through the volumes, this major new work will provide student and researcher alike with key writings on aesthetics in one convenient, uni…Read more
  •  15
    Music and the Representation of Emotion
    Frontiers of Philosophy in China 8 (2): 332-348. 2013.
  •  27
    In defence of colourization
    British Journal of Aesthetics 28 (4): 368-372. 1988.
  •  144
    The cognitive value of music
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (1): 41-54. 1999.
  •  17
    Defining art responsibly
    British Journal of Aesthetics 37 (1): 57-65. 1997.
  •  20
    Semantic Challenges to Realism (review)
    Dialogue 41 (2): 405-406. 2002.
    Semantic realism is the view that sentences can be true even if speakers cannot know that they are. Anti-realists believe that sentences cannot be true unless speakers can know that they are. The difference between the two positions can be characterized as a dispute about truth conditions. Realists believe that they are objective, that is, they can obtain even though speakers cannot know that they do. Anti-realists believe that truth conditions are always recognizable. Two major lines of argumen…Read more
  •  1
    Art and Knowledge
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (2): 198-200. 2005.
  •  15
    Reality and Reason (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 491-500. 1987.
  •  17
  •  188
    The slingshot argument and the correspondence theory of truth
    Acta Analytica 17 (2): 121-132. 2002.
    The correspondence theory of truth holds that each true sentence corresponds to a discrete fact. Donald Davidson and others have argued (using an argument that has come to be known as the slingshot) that this theory is mistaken, since all true sentences correspond to the same “Great Fact.” The argument is designed to show that by substituting logically equivalent sentences and coreferring terms for each other in the context of sentences of the form ‘P corresponds to the fact that P’ every true s…Read more
  •  81
    Global anti-realism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (4): 641-647. 1987.
  •  235
    Truth, correspondence and deflationism
    Frontiers of Philosophy in China 4 (4): 563-575. 2009.
    The central claim of this essay is that many deflationary theories of truth are variants of the correspondence theory of truth. Essential to the correspondence theory of truth is the proposal that objective features of the world are the truthmakers of statements. Many advocates of deflationary theories (including F. P. Ramsay, P. F. Strawson and Paul Horwich) remain committed to this proposal. Although T-sentences (statements of the form “ s is true iff p ”) are presented by advocates of deflati…Read more
  •  12
    Charles Batteux: The Fine Arts Reduced to a Single Principle (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    The Fine Arts Reduced to a Single Principle by Charles Batteux was arguably the most influential work on aesthetics published in the 18th century. James O. Young presents the first complete English translation of the work, with full annotations and a comprehensive introduction, which illuminate Batteux's continuing philosophical interest.
  •  2
    Authenticity in performance
    In Berys Nigel Gaut & Dominic Lopes (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, Routledge. 2000.
  •  74
    Artworks and artworlds
    British Journal of Aesthetics 35 (4): 330-337. 1995.
  • Michael Dummett, Thought and Reality
    Philosophy in Review 27 (5): 334. 2007.
  •  40
    Inquiry in the Arts and Sciences
    Philosophy 71 (276): 255-273. 1996.
    In his 1836 lectures to the Royal Institute, the great landscape painter John Constable stated that ‘Painting is a science, and should be pursued as an inquiry into the laws of nature.’ Landscape, he went on to say, should ‘be considered a branch of natural philosophy, of which pictures are but the experiments.’1Constable makes two claims in this striking passage. The first is that painting is a form of inquiry. This is, by itself, a bold claim, but Constable goes on to state that painters and s…Read more
  •  64
    The ‘great divide’ in music
    British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (2): 175-184. 2005.
    Several prominent philosophers of music, including Lydia Goehr and Peter Kivy, maintain that the experience of music changed drastically in about 1800. According to the great divide hypothesis, prior to 1800 audiences often scarcely attended to music. At other times, music was appreciated as part of social, civic, or religious ceremonies. After the great divide, audiences began to appreciate music as an exclusive object of aesthetic experience. The great divide hypothesis is false. The musicolog…Read more
  •  97
    Destroying works of art
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (4): 367-373. 1989.
  •  63
    Between rock and a Harp place
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1): 78-81. 1995.
  •  102
    Art and the educated audience
    Journal of Aesthetic Education 44 (3): 29-42. 2010.
    When writing about art, aestheticians tend to focus on the work of art and on the artist who produces it. When they refer to audiences, they typically speak only of the effect that the artwork has on its audience. Aestheticians pay little, if any, attention to the important active role that an audience plays in the workings of a healthy art world. My goal in this essay is to do something to end the neglect of the audience. I will focus on the role of the informed or, as I will call it, educated …Read more