•  20
    Het bereik van het mentale
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 74 (1): 103. 2012.
  • Is bewustzijn louter representatie?
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 2 157-159. 2005.
  •  24
    Editorial introduction
    Synthese 129 (1): 1-2. 2001.
    Music raises many problems for those who would understand it more deeply. It is rooted in time, yet timeless. It is pure form, yet conveys emotion. It is written, but performed, interpreted, improvised, transcribed, recorded, sampled, remixed, revised, rebroadcast, reinterpreted, and more. Music can be studied by philosophers, psychologists, sociologists, mathematicians, biologists, computer scientists, neuro-scientists, critics, politicians, promoters, and of course musicians. Moreover, no sing…Read more
  • A way to naturalize phenomenology
    with J. K. O'Regan
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (1): 27-46. 2002.
  • Uitgebreid, complementair, of omvattend? Het waar en het hoe van het mentale
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 104 (3). 2012.
  •  123
  •  21
    Fragmentation, coherence, and the perception/action divide
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (2): 231-231. 2001.
    I discuss Stoffregen & Bardy's theory from the perspective of the complementary aspect of input conflict, namely, imput coherence - the unity of perception. In a classical approach this leads to the famous The conceptual framework the authors construct leaves no space for a binding problem to arise. A remaining problem of perceptual conflict, arising in cases of inversion of the visual field can be handled by the theory the authors propose
  •  32
    Constrained inversions of sensations
    Philosophica (Belgium) 68 (2): 31-40. 2001.
    Inverted sensation arguments such as the inverted spectrum thought experiment are often criticized for relying on an unconstrained notion of 'qualia'. In reply to this criticism, 'qualia-free' arguments for inversion have been proposed, in which only physical changes happen: inversions in the world, such as the replacement of surface colors by their complements, and a rewiring of peripheral input cables to more central areas in the nervous system. I show why such constrained inversion arguments …Read more
  •  73
    Las meninas and the illusion of illusionism
    with Johan Veldeman
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 15 (9): 124-130. 2008.
    There is a popular view on depiction which holds that convincingly realistic paintings depict their subjects through evoking in the spectator the illusion of seeing these very subjects face to face. There is, as it were, an exact 'match' between the visual experience of seeing something in a picture and the corresponding visual experience one would entertain if one were to stand in front of the real thing. This view, which we shall call 'illusionism', supports the widespread assumption that some…Read more
  •  604
    Representation-hunger reconsidered
    with Jan Degenaar
    Synthese 191 (15): 3639-3648. 2014.
    According to a standard representationalist view cognitive capacities depend on internal content-carrying states. Recent alternatives to this view have been met with the reaction that they have, at best, limited scope, because a large range of cognitive phenomena—those involving absent and abstract features—require representational explanations. Here we challenge the idea that the consideration of cognition regarding the absent and the abstract can move the debate about representationalism along…Read more
  •  45
    Trading in form for content and taking the sting out of the mind-body problem
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (6): 766-766. 1998.
    Analytical isomorphism is an instance of the demand for a transparent relation between vehicle and content, which is central to the mind-body problem. One can abandon transparency without begging the question with regard to the mind-body problem.
  •  61
    Perceptual consciousness, access to modality and skill theories: A way to naturalize phenomenology?
    with J. Kevin O'Regan
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (1): 27-45. 2002.
    We address the thesis recently proposed by Andy Clark, that skill-mediated access to modality implies phenomenal feel. We agree that a skill theory of perception does indeed offer the possibility of a satisfactory account of the feel of perception, but we claim that this is not only through explanation of access to modality but also because skill actually provides access to perceptual property in general. We illustrate and substantiate our claims by reference to the recently proposed 'sensorimot…Read more
  •  10
    Eerst iets anders
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 108 (2): 173-177. 2016.
    Amsterdam University Press is a leading publisher of academic books, journals and textbooks in the Humanities and Social Sciences. Our aim is to make current research available to scholars, students, innovators, and the general public. AUP stands for scholarly excellence, global presence, and engagement with the international academic community.
  •  38
    Beyond intrinsicness and dazzling blacks
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (6): 964-965. 1999.
    Palmer's target article is surely one of the most scientifically detailed and knowledgeable treatments of spectrum inversion ever. Unfortunately, it is built on a very shaky philosophical foundation, the notion of the "intrinsic". In the article's ontology, there are two kinds of properties of mental states, intrinsic properties and relational properties. The whole point of the article is that these aspects of experience are mutually exclusive: the intrinsic is nonrelational and the relational i…Read more
  •  36
    Phenomenal consciousness lite: No thanks!
    with J. Kevin O'Regan
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 520-521. 2007.
    The target article appeals to recent empirical data to support the idea that there is more to phenomenality than is available to access consciousness. However, this claim is based on an unwarranted assumption, namely, that some kind of cortical processing must be phenomenal. The article also considerably weakens Block's original distinction between a truly nonfunctional phenomenal consciousness and a functional access consciousness. The new form of phenomenal consciousness seems to be a poor-man…Read more
  •  274
    Sensory consciousness explained (better) in terms of 'corporality' and 'alerting capacity'
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4 (4): 369-387. 2005.
    How could neural processes be associated with phenomenal consciousness? We present a way to answer this question by taking the counterintuitive stance that the sensory feel of an experience is not a thing that happens to us, but a thing we do: a skill we exercise. By additionally noting that sensory systems possess two important, objectively measurable properties, corporality and alerting capacity, we are able to explain why sensory experience possesses a sensory feel, but thinking and other men…Read more
  •  49
    Getting real about experience
    with Inez Myin-Germeys
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (6): 801-802. 2004.
    The idea that experience is essentially subjective rather than of the real world is paradoxical and deeply flawed. The external world is, much more than a mere constraint, essential to meaningfully describe experience and neural activity. This is illustrated by an analysis of the phenomenology of veridical perception and by the study of experience in psychopathology by the Experience Sampling Method (ESM).
  •  35
    Constrained Inversions of Sensations
    Philosophica 68 (2). 2001.
    Inverted sensation arguments such as the inverted spectrum thought experiment are often criticized for relying on an unconstrained notion of 'qualia'. In reply to this criticism, 'qualia-free' arguments for inversion have been proposed, in which only physical changes happen: inversions in the world, such as the replacement of surface colors by their complements, and a rewiring of peripheral input cables to more central areas in the nervous system. I show why such constrained inversion arguments …Read more
  •  69
    The structure of color experience and the existence of surface colors
    with Jan Degenaar
    Philosophical Psychology (3): 1-17. 2013.
    Color experience is structured. Some ?unique? colors (red, green, yellow, and blue) appear as ?pure,? or containing no trace of any other color. Others can be considered as a mixture of these colors, or as ?binary colors.? According to a widespread assumption, this unique/binary structure of color experience is to be explained in terms of neurophysiological structuring (e.g., by opponent processes) and has no genuine explanatory basis in the physical stimulus. The argument from structure builds …Read more
  • The matter of the mind. Philosophical essays on psychology, neuroscience, and reduction (review)
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 101 (2): 157-159. 2009.
  •  108
    Color and the duplication assumption
    Synthese 129 (1): 61-77. 2001.
      Susan Hurley has attacked the ''Duplication Assumption'', the assumption thatcreatures with exactly the same internal states could function exactly alike inenvironments that are systematically distorted. She argues that the dynamicalinterdependence of action and perception is highly problematic for the DuplicationAssumption when it involves spatial states and capacities, whereas no such problemsarise when it involves color states and capacities. I will try to establish that theDuplication Assu…Read more
  • Sensory consciousness explained (better) in terms of ÔÇÿcorporalityÔÇÖ and ÔÇÿalerting capacityÔÇÖ
    with J. K. OÔÇÖregan and A. No├ ½
    Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences 4 (4): 369. 2005.
  •  264
    A short review of Consciousness in Action by Susan Hurley
    with Axel Cleeremans
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 3 455-458. 1999.
    Consider Susan Hurley's depiction of mainstream views of the mind: "The mind is a kind of sandwich, and cognition is the filling" (p. 401). This particular sandwich (with perception as the bottom loaf and action as the top loaf) tastes foul to Hurley, who devotes most of "Consciousness in Action" to a systematic and sometimes extraordinarily detailed critique of what has otherwise been dubbed "classical" models of the mind. This critique then provides the basis for her alternative proposal, in w…Read more
  • Holism, functionalism and visual awareness
    Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 31 (1): 3-19. 1998.
  •  50
    Direct self-consciousness (review)
    Psycoloquy. 2000.
    One can distinguish the descriptive view of self-consciousness from the philosophical framework of the theory of nonconceptual content. Propositional attitudes can be ascribed without commitment to the existence of internal states that bear different species of content. The descriptive view can be coupled to this alternative view
  •  44
    An account of color without a subject?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1): 42-43. 2003.
    While color realism is endorsed, Byrne & Hilbert's (B&H's) case for it stretches the notion of “physical property” beyond acceptable bounds. It is argued that a satisfactory account of color should do much more to respond to antirealist intuitions that flow from the specificity of color experience, and a pointer to an approach that does so is provided.