•  38
    Norms of Epistemic Diversity
    Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 3 (1): 23-36. 2006.
    Epistemic diversity is widely approved of by social epistemologists. This paper asks, more specifically, how much epistemic diversity, and what kinds of epistemic diversity are normatively appropriate? Bothlaissez-faireand highly directive approaches to epistemic diversity are rejected in favor of the claim that diversity is a blunt epistemic tool. There are typically a number of different options for adequate diversification. The paper focuses on scientific domains, with particular attention to…Read more
  •  182
    It Isn't The Thought That Counts
    Argumentation 15 (1): 67-75. 2001.
  • CSW Jobs for Philosophers Employment Study
    Apa Newsletter on Feminism and Philosophy 8 (2): 3-6. 2009.
  •  9
    The pragmatic turn in naturalist philosophy of science
    Perspectives on Science 3 (2): 206-230. 1995.
    Creative approaches in recent work in science studies can be usefully connected with ideas from the pragmatic tradition. This article both criticizes and builds on the contemporary pragmatic views of Hacking, Stich, and others. It selects a theme from the work of James and Dewey as a heuristic for a new, and necessary, pragmatic epistemology of science.
  •  70
    Responses to critics
    Perspectives on Science 16 (3). 2008.
    In this paper I respond to the criticisms of Helen Longino, Alan Richardson, Naomi Oreskes and Sharyn Clough. There is discussion of the character of social knowledge, the goals of scientific inquiry, the connections between Social Empiricism and other approaches in science studies, productive and unproductive dissent, and the distinction between empirical and non-empirical decision vectors.
  •  39
    Multivariate Models of Scientific Change
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994. 1994.
    Social scientists regularly make use of multivariate models to describe complex social phenomena. It is argued that this approach is useful for modelling the variety of cognitive and social factors contributing to scientific change, and superior to the integrated models of scientific change currently available. It is also argued that care needs to be taken in drawing normative conclusions: cognitive factors are not instrinsically more "rational" than social factors, nor is it likely that social …Read more
  •  8
    Frank Sulloway's Born to Rebel
    Philosophy of Science 65 (1): 171. 1998.
    Born to Rebel is an innovative and important work with much to say to philosophers of science, as well as historians and sociologists of science. Sulloway uses, successfully, quantitative statistical methods that others have despaired of using to analyze the complexities of historical change. In particular, he investigates scientific decision-making during scientific controversies with a multivariate analysis. The goal is to discern, precisely, the contribution of factors such as religious belie…Read more
  • W. V. Quine, Pursuit Of Truth (review)
    Philosophy in Review 11 284-286. 1991.
  •  37
    On Putnam’s Argument for the Inconsistency of Relativism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 28 (2): 213-220. 1990.
  •  264
    Just a paradigm: evidence-based medicine in epistemological context
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (3): 451-466. 2011.
    Evidence-Based Medicine (EBM) developed from the work of clinical epidemiologists at McMaster University and Oxford University in the 1970s and 1980s and self-consciously presented itself as a "new paradigm" called "evidence-based medicine" in the early 1990s. The techniques of the randomized controlled trial, systematic review and meta-analysis have produced an extensive and powerful body of research. They have also generated a critical literature that raises general concerns about its methods.…Read more
  •  19
    Commentary: Making meaning—a response to Chokr
    Social Epistemology 7 (4). 1993.
    No abstract
  •  42
    The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Medicine (edited book)
    with Jeremy R. Simon and Harold Kincaid
    Routledge. 2016.
    _The_ _Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Medicine _is a comprehensive guide to topics in the fields of epistemology and metaphysics of medicine. It examines traditional topics such as the concept of disease, causality in medicine, the epistemology of the randomized controlled trial, the biopsychosocial model, explanation, clinical judgment and phenomenology of medicine and emerging topics, such as philosophy of epidemiology, measuring harms, the concept of disability, nursing perspectives, ra…Read more
  •  16
    Naturalism and generality
    Philosophical Psychology 8 (4). 1995.
    Naturalistic epistemologists frequently assume that their aim is to identify generalities (i.e. general laws) about the effectiveness of particular reasoning processes and methods. This paper argues that the search for this kind of generality fails. Work that has been done thus far to identify generalities (e.g. by Goldman, Kitcher and Thagard) overlooks both the complexity of reasoning and the relativity of assessments to particular contexts (domain, stage and goal of inquiry). Examples of huma…Read more
  • Part II-Symposia Papers
    In Borchert (ed.), Philosophy of Science, Macmillan. pp. 73--5. 2006.