•  17
    The Problem of Hell
    Philosophical Review 104 (3): 487. 1995.
  • Plantinga's proper function account of warrant
    In J. J. Kvanvig (ed.), Warrant and Contemporary Epistemology, Rowman and Littlefield, Savage, Maryland. 1996.
    Plantinga thus offers an approach that begins by assessing the faculties or abilities of a cognitive system or agent. Once such an assessment is complete, the epistemologist is in a position to infer the epistemic status of the doxastic products of those faculties or abilities.
  •  25
    The Evidentialist Objection
    American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (1). 1983.
  •  53
    Is there an 'us' in 'justification'?
    Synthese 62 (1). 1985.
    A critical question for epistemologists is whether there are any inter-subjective requirements for having a justified belief C whether there is an >us= in >justification=. One recent epistemologist that has addressed this issue is Keith Lehrer. In Knowledge, Lehrer presents a..
  •  4
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion Volume 5 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press UK. 2014.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century. Under the guidance of a distinguished editorial board, it publishes exemplary papers in any area of philosophy of religion.
  •  20
    Comment: Jonathan L. Kvanvig
    Southwest Philosophy Review 1 182-186. 1984.
  •  13
    He Who Lapse Last Lapse Best
    Southwest Philosophy Review 10 (1): 137-146. 1994.
  •  117
    LEMKE has recently taken issue (see ANALYSIS 46.3, June 1986, pp. 138-44) with my claim that no counterfactual causal account of the basing relation is plausible (see ANALYSIS 45.3, June 1985, pp. 153-8). Intuitively, a counterfactual causal account claims that belief is based on evidence if and only if the evidence either causes the belief or would have caused it had the actual cause been absent. This intuitive formulation accounts only for counterfactual causes of level one: events which would…Read more
  •  13
    ``Conservatism and its Virtues"
    Synthese 79 (1): 143-163. 1989.
  •  1
    ``Scientific Naturalism and the Value of Knowledge"
    In Thomas M. Crisp, Matthew Davidson & David Vander Laan (eds.), Knowledge and Reality: Essays in Honor of Alvin Plantinga, Springer. pp. 193-214. 2006.
  • Philosophical reflection concerning heaven and hell has focused on the place of such doctrines in the great monotheistic religions emanating from the religion of the ancient people of Israel--Christianity, Islam, and Judaism. The philosophical issues that arise concerning these doctrines is not limited to such traditions, however. Consider, for example, the doctrine of hell. Any religion promises certain benefits to its adherents, and these benefits require some contrast that befalls, or might b…Read more
  • ``The Value of Knowledge and Truth"
    In D. M. Borchert (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Macmillan Reference Books. 2006.
  •  91
    Warrant and Contemporary Epistemology: Essays in Honor of Plantinga's Theory of Knowledge (edited book)
    Savage, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield. 1996.
    Alvin Plantinga responds to the essays in a concluding chapter.
  •  13
    Omniscience and Eternity: A Reply to Craig
    Faith and Philosophy 18 (3): 369-376. 2001.
    Craig claims that my treatment of temporal indexicals such as ‘now’ is inadequate, and that my theory gives no general account of tense. Craig’s argument misunderstands the theory of indexicals I give, and I show how to extend the theory to give a general account of tense.
  • ``Credulism"
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 101-110. 1984.
  •  7
    Epistemic Luck (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (1): 272-281. 2008.
  •  13
    The Problem of Hell
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (182): 133-134. 1996.
  •  93
    Assertion, Knowledge, and Lotteries
    In P. Greenough & D. Pritchard (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 140--160. 2009.
  •  51
    Jonathan L. Kvanvig presents a new account of rationality, Perspectivalism, which both avoids elevating rationality so that only the most reflective of us are capable of rational beliefs, and avoids reducing it to the level of beasts. He defends optionality about what it is reasonable to think, and provides a framework for rational disagreement.
  •  45
    Divine Transcendence
    Religious Studies 20 (3). 1984.
    representations, for the unconditioned transcendent surpasses every possible conception of a being, including even the conception of a Supreme Being... It is the religious function of atheism ever to remind us that the religious act has to do with the unconditioned transcendent, and that the representations of the Unconditioned are not objects concerning whose existence.., a discussion would be possible. The word >God= involves a double meaning: it connotes the unconditioned transcendent, the ul…Read more
  •  106
    The best defense of the doctrine of the Incarnation implies that traditional Christianity has a special stake in the knowability paradox, a stake not shared by other theistic perspectives or by non-traditional accounts of the Incarnation. Perhaps, this stake is not even shared by antirealism, the view most obviously threatened by the paradox. I argue for these points, concluding that these results put traditional Christianity at a disadvantage compared to other viewpoints, and I close with some …Read more
  •  13
    Joseph Mendola
    International Philosophical Quarterly 29 (2). 1989.
  •  24
    The Intellectual Virtues and the Life of the Mind (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (175): 254. 1994.
  •  32
    Perceiving God (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 11 (2): 311-321. 1994.
  •  274
    The basic notion of justification
    Philosophical Studies 59 (3): 235-261. 1990.
    Epistemologists often offer theories of justification without paying much attention to the variety and diversity of locutions in which the notion of justification appears. For example, consider the following claims which contain some notion of justification: B is a justified belief, S's belief that p is justified, p is justified for S, S is justified in believing that p, S justifiably believes that p, S's believing p is justified, there is justification for S to believe that p, there is justific…Read more
  •  1
    ``Infinitism, Holism, and the Regress Argument"
    In Peter Klein & John Turri (eds.), Infinitism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2012.