•  138
    Pointless truth
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 32 (1): 199-212. 2008.
    No Abstract
  • Divine Omniscience
    In Adrian Hastings, Alistair Mason & Hugh Pyper (eds.), The Oxford Companion to Christian Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 498-499. 2000.
  •  9
    Truth is Not the Primary Epistemic Goal
    In Matthias Steup & John Turri (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Blackwell. pp. 285-295. 2013.
  •  58
    Intellectual Humility: Lessons from the Preface Paradox
    Res Philosophica 93 (3): 1-532. 2016.
    One response to the preface paradox—the paradox that arises when each claim in a book is justified for the author and yet in the preface the author avers that errors remain—counsels against the preface belief. It is this line of thought that poses a problem for any view that places a high value on intellectual humility. If we become suspicious of preface beliefs, it will be a challenge to explain how expressions of fallibility and intellectual humility are appropriate, whether voiced verbally or…Read more
  •  2
    Phil 418: Epistemology
    Philosophical Studies 99
  •  178
    Closure principles
    Philosophy Compass 1 (3). 2006.
    A dispute in epistemology has arisen over whether some class of things epistemic (things known or justified, for example) is closed under some operation involving the notion of what follows deductively from members of this class. Very few philosophers these days believe that if you know that p, and p entails q, then you know that q. But many philosophers think that something weaker holds, for instance that if you know that p, and p entails q, then you are in a position to know that p, or if you …Read more
  •  54
    Further Thoughts on Agent Reliabilism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (2): 466-480. 2003.
    Though I find the project significant and unprecedented in this way, I am not convinced that it is entirely successful, and I will try to explain here the grounds of my concern. We can begin with Greco’s list of requirements for an adequate theory of knowledge, and the relationship he sees between simple reliabilism and his own theory, agent reliabilism.
  • ``Hasker on Fatalism"
    Philosophical Studies 67 91-101. 1992.
  •  5
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Volume 7 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press UK. 2016.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century. Under the guidance of a distinguished editorial board, it publishes exemplary papers in any area of philosophy of religion.
  •  393
    Why Should Inquiring Minds Want to Know?
    The Monist 81 (3): 426-451. 1998.
    National Enquirer commercials tell us that some people want to know. I have no idea what such a desire has to do with reading tabloid journalism, but the avowal of wanting to know interests me. Maybe this desire is shared by all; at the very least, curiosity is universal. Curiosity may amount to a desire for knowledge, or perhaps it might be explained in other terms, such as a desire for understanding or for finding the truth. Perhaps none of these, even. Maybe the desire is only one of being ab…Read more
  •  158
    Coherentists' Distractions
    Philosophical Topics 23 (1): 257-274. 1995.
    The heart of coherentism is found in two aspects, one negative and one positive. On the negative side, coherentism is a contrary of foundationalism, the view that the epistemic status of our beliefs ultimately traces to, or derives from, basic beliefs.
  • Five Questions about Epistemology
    In Duncan Pritchard & Vincent Hendricks (eds.), Epistemology: 5 Questions, Automatic Press/vip. 2008.
  • ``The Rational Significance of Reflective Ascent"
    In Trent Dougherty (ed.), Evidentialism and its Critics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  8
    ``On Behalf of Maverick Molinism"
    Faith and Philosophy 19 (3): 348-357. 2002.
  •  122
    Can a coherence theory appeal to appearance states?
    Philosophical Studies 67 (3): 197-217. 1992.
    Coherence theorists have universally defined justification as a relation only among (the contents of) belief states, in contradistinction to other theories, such as some versions of founda­tionalism, which define justification as a relation on belief states and appearance states.
  •  231
    Reply to Simion
    Logos and Episteme 8 (1): 113-116. 2017.
    Mona Simion questions whether there is a distinction between taking back an assertion and taking back only the content of an assertion, as I have claimed. After arguing against the distinction in question, Simion grants that there is a difference between the cases that I use to illustrate the distinction, and thus turns to the task of explaining the difference in a way that keeps it from undermining the knowledge norm. The explanation she offers is in terms of a distinction between doing somethi…Read more
  •  50
  •  47
    The Intellectual Virtues and the Life of the Mind (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (4): 973-976. 1994.
  •  41
    ``Nozickian Epistemology and the Question of Closure"
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3): 351-364. 2004.
    Nozick’s contribution to the epistemology of the last half of the twentieth century includes addressing the question of whether knowledge is closed under known implication. I argue that the question of closure provides a serious obstacle to Nozickian approaches to epistemology
  •  140
    Affective Theism and People of Faith
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 37 (1): 109-128. 2013.
  • ``Resurrection, Heaven, and Hell"
    In Charles Taliaferro & Paul Draper (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Routledge. pp. 630-639. 2009.