•  10
    Review of Jonathan L. Kvanvig: The Problem of Hell (review)
    Ethics 105 (4): 961-963. 1995.
  •  43
    Sosa's virtue epistemology
    Critica 42 (125): 47-62. 2010.
    Ernest Sosa's latest epistemology remains a version of virtue epistemology, and I argue here that it faces two central problems, pressing a point I have made elsewhere, that virtue epistemology does not present a complete answer to the problem of the value of knowledge. I will press this point regarding the nature of knowledge through variations on two standard Gettier examples here. The first is the Fake Barn case and the second is the Tom Grabit case. I will argue that Sosa's latest virtue epi…Read more
  •  7
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion Volume 8 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2017.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century.
  •  2
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion Volume 4 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2012.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century.
  •  5
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion Volume 5 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2014.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century.
  •  2
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion: Volume 2 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2009.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century.
  •  4
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion Volume 6 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century.
  •  9
    Warrant and Contemporary Epistemology (edited book)
    Rowman & Littlefield. 1996.
    Motivated by Plantinga's work, fourteen prominent philosophers have written new essays investigating Plantingian warrant and its contribution to contemporary epistemology. The resulting collection, representing a broad array of views, not only gives readers a critical perspective on Plantinga's landmark work, but also provides in one volume a clear statement of the variety of approaches to the nature of warrant within contemporary epistemology and to the connections between epistemology and meta…Read more
  •  89
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion: Volume 1 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is a new annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy ...
  •  40
    Truth and superassertibility
    Philosophical Studies 93 (1): 1-19. 1999.
  •  4
    Perspectivalism and Reflective Assent
    In David Christensen & Jennifer Lackey (eds.), The Epistemology of Disagreement: New Essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 223-242. 2013.
  •  56
    Intellectual Humility: Lessons from the Preface Paradox
    Res Philosophica 93 (3): 1-532. 2016.
    One response to the preface paradox—the paradox that arises when each claim in a book is justified for the author and yet in the preface the author avers that errors remain—counsels against the preface belief. It is this line of thought that poses a problem for any view that places a high value on intellectual humility. If we become suspicious of preface beliefs, it will be a challenge to explain how expressions of fallibility and intellectual humility are appropriate, whether voiced verbally or…Read more
  •  72
    Zagzebski on Justification (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 191--196. 2000.
    The heart of the epistemological interest of Zagzebski’s book is found in the tasks of clarifying the natures of justification and knowledge in terms of the intellectual virtues. It is in virtue of undertaking this task that Zagzebski presents a version of virtue epistemology. Though the book has several interesting features apart from this task, I want to argue that in its fundamental tasks, the book is a failure. In particular, I will argue that Zagzebski’s virtue account of justification is i…Read more
  •  2
    Phil 418: Epistemology
    Philosophical Studies 99
  •  177
    Closure principles
    Philosophy Compass 1 (3). 2006.
    A dispute in epistemology has arisen over whether some class of things epistemic (things known or justified, for example) is closed under some operation involving the notion of what follows deductively from members of this class. Very few philosophers these days believe that if you know that p, and p entails q, then you know that q. But many philosophers think that something weaker holds, for instance that if you know that p, and p entails q, then you are in a position to know that p, or if you …Read more
  •  9
    Truth is Not the Primary Epistemic Goal
    In Matthias Steup & John Turri (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Blackwell. pp. 285-295. 2013.
  • ``Hasker on Fatalism"
    Philosophical Studies 67 91-101. 1992.
  • Unknowable Truths and the Doctrine of Omniscience
    Journal of the American Academy of Religion 57 485-507. 1989.
    THE DOCTRINE OF omniscience has been understood in two ways. Roughly, it has been taken either as the claim that God knows all that is true (Geach, Kvanvig 1986) or as the claim that God knows all that can be known (Swinbume; Mavrodes). The first construal I shall call the traditional construal, and the second I shall call a limited construal. Though the traditional construal would seem to be the natural one to hold, considerations of the analogy between the best construals of the doctrine of om…Read more
  •  4
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Volume 7 (edited book)
    Oxford University Press UK. 2016.
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion is an annual volume offering a regular snapshot of state-of-the-art work in this longstanding area of philosophy that has seen an explosive growth of interest over the past half century. Under the guidance of a distinguished editorial board, it publishes exemplary papers in any area of philosophy of religion.
  •  156
    Coherentists' Distractions
    Philosophical Topics 23 (1): 257-274. 1995.
    The heart of coherentism is found in two aspects, one negative and one positive. On the negative side, coherentism is a contrary of foundationalism, the view that the epistemic status of our beliefs ultimately traces to, or derives from, basic beliefs.
  •  54
    Further Thoughts on Agent Reliabilism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (2): 466-480. 2003.
    Though I find the project significant and unprecedented in this way, I am not convinced that it is entirely successful, and I will try to explain here the grounds of my concern. We can begin with Greco’s list of requirements for an adequate theory of knowledge, and the relationship he sees between simple reliabilism and his own theory, agent reliabilism.
  • ``The Rational Significance of Reflective Ascent"
    In Trent Dougherty (ed.), Evidentialism and its Critics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  8
    ``On Behalf of Maverick Molinism"
    Faith and Philosophy 19 (3): 348-357. 2002.
  •  121
    Can a coherence theory appeal to appearance states?
    Philosophical Studies 67 (3): 197-217. 1992.
    Coherence theorists have universally defined justification as a relation only among (the contents of) belief states, in contradistinction to other theories, such as some versions of founda­tionalism, which define justification as a relation on belief states and appearance states.
  •  225
    Reply to Simion
    Logos and Episteme 8 (1): 113-116. 2017.
    Mona Simion questions whether there is a distinction between taking back an assertion and taking back only the content of an assertion, as I have claimed. After arguing against the distinction in question, Simion grants that there is a difference between the cases that I use to illustrate the distinction, and thus turns to the task of explaining the difference in a way that keeps it from undermining the knowledge norm. The explanation she offers is in terms of a distinction between doing somethi…Read more
  • Five Questions about Epistemology
    In Duncan Pritchard & Vincent Hendricks (eds.), Epistemology: 5 Questions, Automatic Press/vip. 2008.
  •  45
    The Intellectual Virtues and the Life of the Mind (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (4): 973-976. 1994.
  •  41
    ``Nozickian Epistemology and the Question of Closure"
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3): 351-364. 2004.
    Nozick’s contribution to the epistemology of the last half of the twentieth century includes addressing the question of whether knowledge is closed under known implication. I argue that the question of closure provides a serious obstacle to Nozickian approaches to epistemology
  •  139
    Affective Theism and People of Faith
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 37 (1): 109-128. 2013.
  • ``Resurrection, Heaven, and Hell"
    In Charles Taliaferro & Paul Draper (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Routledge. pp. 630-639. 2009.