•  89
    Review: Religious commitment and secular reason (review)
    Mind 111 (443): 639-643. 2002.
  •  35
    Have biologists wrapped up philosophy?
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 43 (2). 2000.
    An examination of the currently fashionable thesis that scientists, and especially biologists in the wake of the Darwinian Revolution, can now solve the problems that traditional philosophers have only talked about. Past philosophers, for example during the Enlightenment, have themselves made use of contemporary, scientific techniques and theories. The present claim may only be another such move, to be welcomed by philosophers who would distinguish themselves from rhetoricians. Others may prefer…Read more
  •  53
  •  116
    The evolution of language: Truth and lies
    Philosophy 75 (3): 401-421. 2000.
    There is both theoretical and experimental reason to suppose that no-one could ever have learned to speak without an environment of language-users. How then did the first language-users learn? Animal communication systems provide no help, since human languages aren't constituted as a natural system of signs, and are essentially recursive and syntactic. Such languages aren't demanded by evolution, since most creatures, even intelligent creatures, manage very well without them. I propose that repr…Read more
  • Nothing without mind
    In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Consciousness Evolving, John Benjamins. 2002.
  •  61
    Non-personal minds
    In Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, Cambridge University Press. pp. 185-209. 2003.
    Persons are creatures with a range of personal capacities. Most known to us are also people, though nothing in observation or biological theory demands that all and only people are persons, nor even that persons, any more than people, constitute a natural kind. My aim is to consider what non-personal minds are like. Darwin's Earthworms are sensitive, passionate and, in their degree, intelligent. They may even construct maps, embedded in the world they perceive around them, so as to be able to co…Read more
  •  1
    The description and evaluation of animal emotion
    In Colin Blakemore & Susan A. Greenfield (eds.), Mindwaves, Blackwell. 1987.
  •  69
    Minds, memes, and multiples
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (1): 21-28. 1996.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Minds, Memes, and MultiplesStephen R. L. Clark (bio)AbstractMultiple Personality Disorder is sometimes interpreted as evidence for a radically pluralistic theory of the human mind, judged to be at odds with an older, monistic theory. Older philosophy, on the contrary, suggests that the mind is both plural (in its sub-systems or personalities) and unitary (in that there is only one light over all those lesser parts). Talk of gods and …Read more
  •  77
    Minds, memes, and rhetoric
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 36 (1-2): 3-16. 1993.
    Dennett's Consciousness Explained presents, but does not demonstrate, a fully naturalized account of consciousness that manages to leave out the very consciousness he purports to explain. If he were correct, realism and methodological individualism would collapse, as would the very enterprise of giving reasons. The metaphors he deploys actually testify to the power of metaphoric imagination that can no more be identified with the metaphors it creates than minds can be identified with memes. That…Read more
  •  41
    Slaves and Citizens
    Philosophy 60 (231): 27-. 1985.
    R. M. Hare has argued 1 that there are conceivable circumstances in which it would be right not to abolish the institution of slavery: in the imaginary land of Juba established slave-plantations are managed by a benevolent elite for the good of all, no ‘cruel or unusual ’ punishments are in use, and citizens of the neighbouring island of Camaica, ‘free ’but impoverished, regularly seek to become slaves. Hare adds that it is unlikely, given human nature, that ‘masters ’would treat ‘slaves ’humane…Read more
  • Implications of Socio-Cultural Contexts for the Ethics of Clinical Trials
    with Richard E. Ashcroft, D. Chadwick, Richard H. T. Edwards, and Lucy Frith
    Core Research. 1997.
  •  5
    Form and Transformation: a study in the philosophy of Plotinus
    Philosophical Books 36 (1): 40-42. 1995.
  •  18
    Plotinus (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 34 (3): 382-384. 1994.
  •  26
    Patrides, Plotinus and the Cambridge Platonists
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (5): 858-877. 2017.
    Discussion of the Cambridge Platonists, by Constantinos Patrides and others, is often vitiated by the mistaken contrasts drawn between those philosophers and late antique Platonists such as Plotinus. I draw attention especially to Patrides’s errors, and argue in particular that Plotinus and his immediate followers were as concerned about this world and our immediate duties to our neighbours as the Cambridge Platonists. Even the doctrine of deification is one shared by all Platonists, though it i…Read more
  •  36
    Plotinus on intellect – eyjólfur kjalar Emilsson
    Philosophical Quarterly 59 (235): 357-359. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  19
    In composing this study of 'Ancient Mediterranean Philosophy', I have chosen to draw attention to other philosophical traditions than the Classical Greek and Latin , although we know much less about them. My working assumption is that ...
  •  69
    The rights of wild things
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22 (1-4). 1979.
    It has been argued that if non-human animals had rights we should be obliged to defend them against predators. I contend that this either does not follow, follows in the abstract but not in practice, or is not absurd. We should defend non-humans against large or unusual dangers, when we can, but should not claim so much authority as to regulate all the relationships of wild things. Some non-human animals are members of our society, and the rhetoric of 'the land as a community' is an attempt, par…Read more
  •  535
    How to Become Unconscious
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 67 21-44. 2010.
    Consistent materialists are almost bound to suggest that , if it exists at all, is no more than epiphenomenal. A correct understanding of the real requires that everything we do and say is no more than a product of whatever processes are best described by physics, without any privileged place, person, time or scale of action. Consciousness is a myth, or at least a figment. Plotinus was no materialist: for him, it is Soul and Intellect that are more real than the phenomena we misdescribe as mater…Read more
  •  1
    How the 'Aristotelian' biological synthesis has been affected by modern accounts of biological evolution, and the relation of taxonomy to ethics.
  •  18
    Riots at Brightlingsea
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 13 (1): 109-112. 1996.
  •  7
    A parliament of souls
    Oxford University Press. 1990.
    This second volume in the Limits and Renewals trilogy is an attempt to restate a traditional philosophy of mind, drawing on philosophical and poetical resources that are often neglected in modern and postmodern thought, and emphasizing the moral and political implications of differing philosophies of mind and value. Clark argues that without the traditional concept of the soul, we have little reason to believe that rational thought and individual autonomy are either possible or desirable. The pa…Read more
  •  394
    Folly to the Greeks: Good Reasons to Give up Reason
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (1): 93-113. 2012.
    A discussion of why a strong doctrine of 'reason' may not be worth sustaining in the face of modern scientific speculation, and the difficulties this poses for scientific rationality, together with comments on the social understanding of religion, and why we might wish to transcend common sense.