•  825
    Omissions, Responsibility, and Symmetry
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (3): 594-624. 2011.
    It is widely held that one can be responsible for doing something that one was unable to avoid doing. This paper focuses primarily on the question of whether one can be responsible for not doing something that one was unable to do. The paper begins with an examination of the account of responsibility for omissions offered by John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, arguing that in many cases it yields mistaken verdicts. An alternative account is sketched that jibes with and explains judgments about…Read more
  •  367
    Agent causation and the problem of luck
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (3): 408-421. 2005.
    : On a standard libertarian account of free will, an agent acts freely on some occasion only if there remains, until the action is performed, some chance that the agent will do something else instead right then. These views face the objection that, in such a case, it is a matter of luck whether the agent does one thing or another. This paper considers the problem of luck as it bears on agent‐causal libertarian accounts. A view of this type is defended against a recent and challenging version of …Read more
  •  583
    Free Will and Agential Powers
    with Thomas Reed
    Oxford Studies in Agency and Moral Responsibility 3 6-33. 2015.
    Free will is often said—by compatibilists and incompatibilists alike—to be a power (or complex of powers) of agents. This paper offers proposals for, and examines the prospects of, a powers-conception of free will that takes the powers in question to be causal dispositions. A difficulty for such an account stems from the idea that when one exercises free will, it is up to oneself whether one wills to do this or that. The paper also briefly considers whether a powers-conception that invokes power…Read more
  •  152
  •  108
    Determinism and our self-conception (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (1): 242-250. 2009.
    This paper is a contribution to a symposium on John Fischer's MY WAY. In much of that work, Fischer says, he aims to show the "resiliency of our fundamental conception of ourselves as possessing control and being morally responsible agents," and particularly the compatibility of that conception with determinism. I argue that his conclusions leave several important aspects of our ordinary conception of our agency hostage to determinism. Further, there is significant tension between certain of his…Read more
  •  27
    The Metaphysics of Free Will: An Essay on Control (review)
    Philosophical Review 106 (3): 450. 1997.
    The first, the Transfer Version, employs an inference principle concerning the transfer of one's powerlessness with respect to certain facts. The principle says, roughly, "If a person is powerless over one thing, and powerless over that thing's leading to another, then the person is powerless over the second thing". The key premises are the Fixity of the Past and the Fixity of the Laws. Fischer defends the transfer principle against objections that have been raised by Anthony Kenny and Michael S…Read more
  •  198
    Abilities to Act
    Philosophy Compass 10 (12): 893-904. 2015.
    This essay examines recent work on abilities to act. Different kinds of ability are distinguished, and a recently proposed conditional analysis of ability ascriptions is evaluated. It is considered whether abilities are causal powers. Finally, several compatibility questions concerning abilities, as well as the relation between free will and abilities of various kinds, are examined
  •  135
  •  500
    On an argument for the impossibility of moral responsibility
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29 (1): 13-24. 2005.
    Galen Strawson has published several versions of an argument to the effect that moral responsibility is impossible, whether determinism is true or not. Few philosophers have been persuaded by the argument, which Strawson remarks is often dismissed “as wrong, or irrelevant, or fatuous, or too rapid, or an expression of metaphysical megalomania.” I offer here a two-part explanation of why Strawson’s argument has impressed so few. First, as he usually states it, the argument is lacking at least one…Read more
  •  668
    Agency and Incompatibilism (review)
    Res Philosophica 91 (3): 519-525. 2014.
    This paper is part of a symposium discussing Helen Steward's A METAPHYSICS FOR FREEDOM. Steward argues for what she calls Agency Incompatibilism: agency itself is incompatible with determinism. This paper examines what Steward presents as her main argument for Agency Incompatibilism and finds it wanting.
  •  239
    Intentional omissions
    Noûs 44 (1): 158-177. 2010.
    It is argued that intentionally omitting requires having an intention with relevant content. And the intention must play a causal role with respect to one’s subsequent thought and conduct. Even if omissions cannot be caused, an account of intentional omission must be causal. There is a causal role for one’s reasons as well when one intentionally omits to do something.
  • Freedom and responsibility
    In John Skorupski (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Ethics, Routledge. 2010.
    This entry in THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO ETHICS examines moral responsibility and the freedom required for responsibility. The nature of responsibility, its compatibility with determinism, and whether responsibility is impossible are among the topics examined.
  •  86
    Willing, wanting, waiting * by Richard Holton (review)
    Analysis 71 (1): 191-193. 2011.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  923
    Many philosophical theories of causation are egalitarian, rejecting a distinction between causes and mere causal conditions. We sought to determine the extent to which people's causal judgments discriminate, selecting as causes counternormal events—those that violate norms of some kind—while rejecting non-violators. We found significant selectivity of this sort. Moreover, priming that encouraged more egalitarian judgments had little effect on subjects. We also found that omissions are as likely …Read more
  •  297
    Skilled activity and the causal theory of action
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (3): 523-550. 2010.
    Skilled activity, such as shaving or dancing, differs in important ways from many of the stock examples that are employed by action theorists. Some critics of the causal theory of action contend that such a view founders on the problem of skilled activity. This paper examines how a causal theory can be extended to the case of skilled activity and defends the account from its critics.
  •  100
    On the possibility of rational free action
    Philosophical Studies 88 (1): 37-57. 1997.
  •  540
    Absence of action
    Philosophical Studies 158 (2): 361-376. 2012.
    Often when one omits to do a certain thing, there's no action that is one's omission; one's omission, it seems, is an absence of any action of some type. This paper advances the view that an absence of an action--and, in general, any absence--is nothing at all: there is nothing that is an absence. Nevertheless, it can result from prior events that one omits to do a certain thing, and there can be results of the fact that one omits to do something. This is so even if absences cannot be causes or …Read more
  •  98
    Modest libertarianism
    Noûs 34 (s14): 21-46. 2000.
    This paper examines libertarian accounts that appeal to event causation but avoid appeal to agent causation. Such views are modest in their metaphysical commitments and may be modest, as well, in what they promise. It is argued that an action-centered version should be preferred; on such a view, indeterminism is required in the direct production of decision or other action. Although a view of this kind does not improve on compatibilist accounts when it comes to moral responsibility, they may be …Read more
  •  668
    Some Theses on Desert
    Philosophical Explorations 16 (2): 153-64. 2013.
    Consider the idea that suffering of some specific kind is deserved by those who are guilty of moral wrongdoing. Feeling guilty is a prime example. It might be said that it is noninstrumentally good that one who is guilty feel guilty (at the right time and to the right degree), or that feeling guilty (at the right time and to the right degree) is apt or fitting for one who is guilty. Each of these claims constitutes an interesting thesis about desert, given certain understandings of what desert i…Read more
  •  76
    Indeterminism and control
    American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (2): 125-138. 1995.
  •  542
    This paper examines recent attempts to revive a classic compatibilist position on free will, according to which having an ability to perform a certain action is having a certain disposition. Since having unmanifested dispositions is compatible with determinism, having unexercised abilities to act, it is held, is likewise compatible. Here it is argued that although there is a kind of capacity to act possession of which is a matter of having a disposition, the new dispositionalism leaves unresolve…Read more
  •  37
    The Nature of Moral Responsibility: New Essays
    with Michael McKenna and Angela M. Smith
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    What is it to be morally responsible for something? Recent philosophical work reveals considerable disagreement on the question. Indeed, some theorists claim to distinguish several varieties of moral responsibility, with different conditions that must be satisfied if one is to bear responsibility of one or another of these kinds. Debate on this point turns partly on disagreement about the kinds of responses made appropriate when one is blameworthy or praiseworthy. It is generally agreed that the…Read more