•  59
    Identity, Quantification, and Number
    In T. Tahko (ed.), Contemporary Aristotelian Metaphysics, Cambridge University Press. pp. 66-82. 2012.
    E. J. Lowe and others argue that there can be 'uncountable' things admitting of no numerical description. This implies that there can be something without there being at least one such thing, and that things can be identical without being one or nonidentical without being two. The clearest putative example of uncountable things is portions of homogeneous stuff or 'gunk'. The paper argues that there is a number of portions of gunk if there is any gunk at all, and that the possibility of uncountab…Read more
  •  319
    Dion’s Foot
    Journal of Philosophy 94 (5): 260-265. 1997.
    Suppose a certain man, Dion, has his foot amputated, and lives to tell the tale. That tale involves a well-known metaphysical puzzle, for most of us assume that there was, before the operation, an object made up of all of Dion’s parts except those that overlapped with his foot-- ”all of Dion except for his foot”, we might say, or Dion’s “foot-complement”. Call that object Theon. (Anyone who doubts that there is such a thing as Dion’s undetached foot-complement may imagine that ‘Theon’ is a name …Read more
  •  70
    The Nature of People
    In Steven Luper (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Life and Death, Cambridge University Press. pp. 30-46. 2014.
  •  3
    Animalism and the Remnant-Person Problem
    In João Fonseca & Jorge Gonçalves (eds.), Philosophical Perspectives on the Self, Peter Lang. pp. 21-40. 2015.
  •  577
    The Bodily Criterion of Personal Identity
    In Fraser MacBride (ed.), Identity and Modality, Clarendon Press. pp. 242. 2006.
    One of the main problems of personal identity is supposed to be how we relate to our bodies. A few philosophers endorse what is called a 'bodily criterion of personal identity': they say that we are our bodies, or at any rate that our identity over time consists in the identity of our bodies. Many more deny this--typically on the grounds that we can imagine ourselves coming apart from our bodies. But both sides agree that the bodily criterion is an important view which anyone thinking about pers…Read more
  •  163
    Personal identity and the radiation argument
    Analysis 61 (1): 38-44. 2001.
    Sydney Shoemaker has argued that, because we can imagine a people who take themselves to survive a 'brain-state-transfer' procedure, cerebrum transplant, or the like, we ought to conclude that we could survive such a thing. I claim that the argument faces two objections, and can be defended only by depriving it any real interest
  •  375
    What are we?
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 14 (5-6): 37-55. 2007.
    This paper is about the neglected question of what sort of things we are metaphysically speaking. It is different from the mind-body problem and from familiar questions of personal identity. After explaining what the question means and how it differs from others, the paper tries to show how difficult it is to give a satisfying answer
  •  69
    Lowe's defence of constitutionalism
    Philosophical Quarterly 53 (210). 2003.
    Constitutionalism says that qualitatively different objects can be made of the same matter at once. Critics claim that we should expect such objects to be qualitatively indistinguishable. E.J. Lowe thinks this complaint is based on the false assumption that differences in the way things are at a time must always be grounded in how things are at that time, and that we can answer it by pointing out that different kinds of coinciding objects are subject to different composition principles. I argue …Read more
  •  137
    Immanent Causation and Life After Death
    In G. Gasser (ed.), Personal Identity and Resurrection, Ashgate. pp. 51-66. 2010.
    The paper concerns the metaphysical possibility of life after death. It argues that the existence of a psychological duplicate is insufficient for resurrection, even if psychological continuity suffices for personal identity. That is because our persistence requires immanent causation. There are at most three ways of having life after death: if we are immaterial souls; if we are snatched bodily from our deathbeds; or if there is immanent causation ‘at a distance’ as Zimmerman proposes--but this …Read more
  •  191
    The Person and the Corpse
    In Ben Bradley, Fred Feldman & Jens Johansson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death, Oup Usa. pp. 80. 2013.
  • The Human Animal. Personal identity without psychology
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 192 (1): 112-113. 1997.
  •  1190
    The view that we are human animals, " animalism ", is deeply unpopular. This paper explains what that claim says and why it is so contentious. It then argues that those who deny it face an awkward choice. They must either deny that there are any human animals, deny that human animals can think, or deny that we are the thinking things located where we are
  •  317
    Reply to Lynne Rudder Baker
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (1): 161-166. 1999.
    In “Was I Ever a Fetus?” I argued that, since each of us was once an unthinking fetus, psychological continuity cannot be necessary for us to persist through time. Baker claims that the argument is invalid, and that both the premise and the conclusion are false. I attempt to defend argument, premise, and conclusion against her objections.
  •  399
    Was Jekyll Hyde?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (2): 328-348. 2003.
    Many philosophers say that two or more people or thinking beings could share a single human being in a split‐personality case, if only the personalities were sufficiently independent and individually well integrated. I argue that this view is incompatible with our being material things, and conclude that there could never be two or more people in a split‐personality case. This refutes the view, almost universally held, that facts about mental unity and disunity determine how many people there ar…Read more
  •  100
    Critical notice of T. Merricks, Objects and Persons (review)
    Philosophical Books 43 (4): 292-99. 2002.
    Book reviewed in this article T. Merricks, Objects and Persons.
  •  477
    The rate of time's passage
    Analysis 69 (1): 3-9. 2009.
    Many philosophers say that time involves a kind of passage that distinguishes it from space. A traditional objection is that this passage would have to occur at some rate, yet we cannot say what the rate would be. The paper argues that the real problem with time’s passage is different: time would have to pass at one second per second, yet this is not a rate of change. This appears to refute decisively not only the view that time passes, but any tensed theory of time
  •  165
    In Search of the Simple View
    In G. Gasser & M. Stefan (eds.), Personal Identity: Complex or Simple?, Cambridge University Press. forthcoming.
    Accounts of personal identity over time are supposed to fall into two broad categories: 'complex views' saying that our persistence consists in something else, and 'simple views' saying that it doesn' t. But it is impossible to characterize this distinction in any satisfactory way. The debate has been systematically misdescribed. After arguing for this claim, the paper says something about how the debate might be better characterized
  •  12
    Dion’s Foot
    Journal of Philosophy 94 (5): 260. 1997.
  •  84
    The Ontological Basis of Strong Artificial Life
    Artificial Life 3 29-39. 1997.
    This article concerns the claim that it is possible to create living organisms, not merely models that represent organisms, simply by programming computers. I ask what sort of things these computer-generated organisms are supposed to be. I consider four possible answers to this question: The organisms are abstract complexes of pure information; they are material objects made of bits of computer hardware; they are physical processes going on inside the computer; and they are denizens of an entire…Read more
  •  167
    Cartesian or substance dualism is the view that concrete substances come in two basic kinds. There are material things, such as biological organisms. These may be either simple or composed of parts. And there are immaterial things--minds or souls--which are always simple. No material thing depends for its existence on any soul, or vice versa. And only souls can think
  •  451
    The Extended Self
    Minds and Machines 21 (4): 481-495. 2011.
    The extended-mind thesis says that mental states can extend beyond one’s skin. Clark and Chalmers infer from this that the subjects of such states also extend beyond their skin: the extended-self thesis. The paper asks what exactly the extended-self thesis says, whether it really does follow from the extended-mind thesis, and what it would mean if it were true. It concludes that the extended-self thesis is unattractive, and does not follow from the extended mind unless thinking beings are litera…Read more
  •  16
    Replies
    Abstracta 4 (S1): 32-42. 2008.
  •  286
    What are we?: a study in personal ontology
    Oxford University Press. 2007.
    From the time of Locke, discussions of personal identity have often ignored the question of our basic metaphysical nature: whether we human people are biological organisms, spatial or temporal parts of organisms, bundles of perceptions, or what have you. The result of this neglect has been centuries of wild proposals and clashing intuitions. What Are We? is the first general study of this important question. It beings by explaining what the question means and how it differs from others, such as …Read more
  •  220
    Material coincidence and the indiscernibility problem
    Philosophical Quarterly 51 (204): 337-355. 2001.
    It is often said that the same particles can simultaneously make up two or more material objects that differ in kind and in their mental, biological, and other qualitative properties. Others wonder how objects made of the same parts in the same arrangement and surroundings could differ in these ways. I clarify this worry and show that attempts to dismiss or solve it miss its point. At most one can argue that it is a problem we can live with
  •  137
    Imperfect identity
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (2). 2006.
    That grass is green, that pigs don’t fly, and that you are now awake are all hard facts. But there is often said to be something soft about matters of identity over time. Is today’s village church the very church that was first built here, despite centuries of repairs and alterations? How many parts of my bicycle do I need to replace before I get a numerically different bike? If a club disbands and years later some of the original members start a similar club with the same name, have we got two …Read more
  •  128
    The passage of time
    In Robin Le Poidevin, Simons Peter, McGonigal Andrew & Ross P. Cameron (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, Routledge. 2009.
    The prosaic content of these sayings is that events change from future to present and from present to past. Your next birthday is in the future, but with the passage of time it draws nearer and nearer until it is present. 24 hours later it will be in the past, and then lapse forever deeper into history. And things get older: even if they don’t wear out or lose their hair or change in any other way, their chronological age is always increasing. These changes are universal and inescapable: no even…Read more
  •  217
    Composition and coincidence
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (4): 374-403. 1996.
    Many philosophers say that the same atoms may compose at once a statue and a lump of matter that could outlive the statue. I reject this because no difference between the statue and the lump could explain why they have different persistence conditions. But if we say that the lump is the statue, it is difficult to see how there could be any human beings. I argue that this and analogous problems about material objects admit only of solutions that at least appear to be radically at odds with our or…Read more
  •  409
    There is no problem of the self
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 5 (5-6): 645-657. 1998.
    Because there is no agreed use of the term 'self', or characteristic features or even paradigm cases of selves, there is no idea of "the self" to figure in philosophical problems. The term leads to troubles otherwise avoidable; and because legitimate discussions under the heading of 'self' are really about other things, it is gratuitous. I propose that we stop speaking of selves
  •  447
    Animalism and the corpse problem
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (2): 265-74. 2004.
    The apparent fact that each of us coincides with a thinking animal looks like a strong argument for our being animals (animalism). Some critics, however, claim that this sort of reasoning actually undermines animalism. According to them, the apparent fact that each human animal coincides with a thinking body that is not an animal is an equally strong argument for our not being animals. I argue that the critics' case fails for reasons that do not affect the case for animalism.