•  23
    Narrative Explanation and Non-Epistemic Value
    Journal of the Philosophy of History 17 (1): 53-76. 2023.
    Explanations in the natural historical sciences often take the form of stories. This paper examines two accounts of the sources of narrative’s explanatory power: Beatty’s suggestion that narrative explanation is closely connected to historical contingency, and that narratives explain by contrasting what happened with what might have happened; and Ereshefsky and Turner’s view that narratives explain by organizing events around a central subject with a distinctive direction of historical developme…Read more
  •  18
    Creativity Without Agency: Evolutionary Flair & Aesthetic Engagement
    with Adrian Currie and Derek Turner*
    Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 10 (n/a). 2023.
    Common philosophical accounts of creativity align creative products and processes with a particular kind of agency: namely, that deserving of praise or blame. Considering evolutionary examples, we explore two ways of denying that creativity requires forms of agency. First, we argue that decoupling creativity from praiseworthiness comes at little cost: accepting that evolutionary processes are non-agential, they nonetheless exhibit many of the same characteristics and value associated with creati…Read more
  •  17
    Are We at War with Nature?
    Environmental Values 14 (1). 2005.
    A number of people, from William James to Dave Foreman and Vandana Shiva, have suggested that humans are at war with nature. Moreover, the analogy with warfare figures in at least one important argument for strategic monkeywrenching. In general, an analogy can be used for purposes of (1) justification; (2) persuasion; or (3) as a tool for generating novel hypotheses and recommendations. This paper argues that the analogy with warfare should not be used for justificatory or rhetorical purposes, b…Read more
  •  11
    Brill Online Books and Journals
    with Rob Inkpen
    Journal of the Philosophy of History 6 (1): 1-19. 2012.
    Starting with Ben-Menahem’s definition of historical contingency as sensitivity to variations in initial conditions, we suggest that historical events and processes can be thought of as forming a complex landscape of contingency and necessity. We suggest three different ways of extending and elaborating Ben-Menahem’s concepts: By supplementing them with a notion of historical disturbance; by pointing out that contingency and necessity are subject to scaling effects; by showing how degrees of con…Read more
  •  9
    Causal History, Environmental Art, and Biotechnologically Assisted Restoration
    Ethics, Policy and Environment 25 (2): 125-128. 2022.
    Eric Katz’s insight about the relationship between causal history and value only generates a principled critique of de-extinction when conjoined with the diminishment claim, or the claim that human involvement in something’s causal history diminishes its value. The diminishment claim is a form of negative anthropocentrism. In addition to thinking about de-extinction as a form of ecological restoration, we could think of it as a form of environmental artwork. This reframing highlights the implaus…Read more
  •  7
    Book Forum
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 98 (C): 7-8. 2023.
  • Evolution and Inquiry: An Analogy
    Dissertation, Vanderbilt University. 2000.
    Part One of this dissertation explores an analogy between Darwinian evolution by natural selection and the process of inquiry. Beliefs are memes, or replicators, much like biological replicators . As beliefs replicate, their numbers can increase at a geometrical rate. Important checks to the replication of beliefs include limited human memory and attention, as well as the law of non-contradiction. When someone detects an inconsistency, the contradictory beliefs enter into an intellectual struggl…Read more