•  520
    Word and Action: Reconciling Rules and Know-How in Moral Cognition
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (sup1): 267-289. 2000.
    Recent work in cognitive science highlights the importance of exem- plar-based know-how in supporting human expertise. Influenced by this model, certain accounts of moral knowledge now stress exemplar- based, non-sentential know-how at the expense of rule-and-principle based accounts. I shall argue, however, that moral thought and reason cannot be understood by reference to either of these roles alone. Moral cognition – like other forms of ‘advanced’ cognition – depends crucially on the subtle i…Read more
  •  306
    How do questions concerning consciousness and phenomenal experience relate to, or interface with, questions concerning plans, knowledge and intentions? At least in the case of visual experience the relation, we shall argue, is tight. Visual perceptual experience, we shall argue, is fixed by an agent’s direct unmediated knowledge concerning her poise (or apparent poise) over a currently enabled action space. An action space, in this specific sense, is to be understood not as a fine-grained matrix…Read more
  •  68
    Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again
    with Tim van Gelder
    Philosophical Review 107 (4): 647. 1998.
    A great deal of philosophy of mind in the modern era has been driven by an intense aversion to Cartesian dualism. In the 1950s, materialists claimed to have succeeded once and for all in exorcising the Cartesian ghost by identifying the mind with the brain. In subsequent decades, cognitive science put scientific meat on this metaphysical skeleton by explicating mental processes as digital computation implemented in the brain's hardware.
  •  38
    Reading the generalizer's mind
    with Chris Thornton
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (2): 308-310. 1998.
    In his new commentary, Damper re-emphasises his claim that parity is not a generalisation problem. But when proper account is taken of the arguments he puts forward, we find that the proposed conclusion is not the only one that can be drawn.
  •  147
    Relational learning re-examined
    with Chris Thornton
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1): 83-83. 1997.
    We argue that existing learning algorithms are often poorly equipped to solve problems involving a certain type of important and widespread regularity that we call “type-2 regularity.” The solution in these cases is to trade achieved representation against computational search. We investigate several ways in which such a trade-off may be pursued including simple incremental learning, modular connectionism, and the developmental hypothesis of “representational redescription.”.
  •  14
    Putting Concepts to Work: Some Thoughts for the Twentyfirst Century
    with Jesse Prinz and Jerry Fodor
    Mind and Language 19 (1): 57-69. 2004.
    Fodor's theory makes thinking prior to doing. It allows for an inactive agent or pure reflector, and for agents whose actions in various ways seem to float free of their own conceptual repertoires. We show that naturally evolved creatures are not like that. In the real world, thinking is always and everywhere about doing. The point of having a brain is to guide the actions of embodied beings in a complex material world. Some of those actions are, to be sure, more recondite than others. But in ev…Read more
  •  49
    Expecting some action: Predictive Processing and the construction of conscious experience
    with Kathryn Nave, George Deane, and Mark Miller
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 13 (4): 1019-1037. 2022.
    Predictive processing has begun to offer new insights into the nature of conscious experience—but the link is not straightforward. A wide variety of systems may be described as predictive machines, raising the question: what differentiates those for which it makes sense to talk about conscious experience? One possible answer lies in the involvement of a higher-order form of prediction error, termed expected free energy. In this paper we explore under what conditions the minimization of this new …Read more
  •  216
    Recent work in cognitive and computational neuroscience depicts the human cortex as a multi-level prediction engine. This ‘predictive processing’ framework shows great promise as a means of both understanding and integrating the core information processing strategies underlying perception, reasoning, and action. But how, if at all, do emotions and sub-cortical contributions fit into this emerging picture? The fit, we shall argue, is both profound and potentially transformative. In the picture we…Read more
  •  38
    Editorial: Predictive Processing and Consciousness
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 13 (4): 797-808. 2022.
  •  32
    In the original publication, funding information was missing: Andy Clark was supported by ERC Advanced Grant 692739.
  •  478
    Selective representing and world-making
    Minds and Machines 12 (3): 383-395. 2002.
    In this paper, we discuss the thesis of selective representing — the idea that the contents of the mental representations had by organisms are highly constrained by the biological niches within which the organisms evolved. While such a thesis has been defended by several authors elsewhere, our primary concern here is to take up the issue of the compatibility of selective representing and realism. In this paper we hope to show three things. First, that the notion of selective representing is full…Read more
  •  118
    Words and the world: predictive coding and the language-perception-cognition interface
    with Gary Lupyan
    Current Directions in Psychological Science 24 (4): 279-284. 2015.
    Can what we know change what we see? Does language affect cognition and perception? The last few years have seen increased attention to these seemingly disparate questions, but with little theoretical advance. We argue that substantial clarity can be gained by considering these questions through the lens of predictive processing, a framework in which mental representations—from the perceptual to the cognitive—reflect an interplay between downward-flowing predictions and upward-flowing sensory si…Read more
  •  56
    Mind, Brain and the Quantum
    Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161): 509-514. 1990.
  •  20
    Microcognition
    with Dan Lloyd
    Philosophical Review 101 (3): 706. 1992.
  •  157
    The emerging neurocomputational vision of humans as embodied, ecologically embedded, social agents—who shape and are shaped by their environment—offers a golden opportunity to revisit and revise ideas about the physical and information-theoretic underpinnings of life, mind, and consciousness itself. In particular, the active inference framework makes it possible to bridge connections from computational neuroscience and robotics/AI to ecological psychology and phenomenology, revealing common unde…Read more
  •  23
  •  106
    Bootstrapping the mind
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1): 41-58. 2008.
    After offering a brief account of how we understand the shared circuits model (SCM), we divide our response into four sections. First, in section R1, we assess to what extent SCM is committed to an account of the ontogeny and phylogeny of shared circuits. In section R2, we examine doubts raised by several commentators as to whether SCM might be expanded so as to accommodate the mirroring of emotions, sensations, and intransitive actions more generally. Section R3 responds to various criticisms t…Read more
  •  22
    Book reviews (review)
    with W. F. G. Haselager, Jay L. Garfield, Carol W. Slater, Louis C. Charland, Charles Siewert, and Mark L. Johnson
    Philosophical Psychology 9 (3): 391-410. 1996.
    The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: a philosophical journey into the brain, Paul M. Churchland. Cambridge: Bradford Books, MIT Press, 1995 ISBN: 0–262–03244–4Cognition in the wild, Edwin Hutchins. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995. ISBN: 0–262–08231–4Dimensions of creativity, Margaret A. Boden, (Ed.) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994 ISBN 0–262–02368–7Contemplating minds: a forum for Artificial Intelligence, William J. Clancey, Stephen W. Smoliar & Mark J. Stefik (Eds) Cambridge: Bradford Book…Read more
  •  8
    Book reviews (review)
    with Jay L. Garfield, Colin Allen, Paul E. Griffiths, David Pitt, J. D. Trout, and Justin Leiber
    Philosophical Psychology 11 (1): 89-109. 1998.
    How to build a theory in cognitive science. Valerie Gray Hardcastle. Albany: State University of New York. Press, 1996Language, thought, and consciousness. Peter Carruthers. Cambridge: Cambridge University. Press, 1996. ISBN 0–521–48158–9 (hc)Young children's knowledge about thinking. John H. Flavell, Frances L. Green & Eleanor R. Flavell with Commentary by Paul L. Harris & Janet Wilde Astington. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 1995, 60 (1, Serial No, 243) Chicago: T…Read more
  •  92
    Free-Energy Minimization and the Dark-Room Problem
    with Karl Friston and Christopher Thornton
    Frontiers in Psychology 3. 2012.
  •  117
    Over the last 30 years, representationalist and dynamicist positions in the philosophy of cognitive science have argued over whether neurocognitive processes should be viewed as representational or not. Major scientific and technological developments over the years have furnished both parties with ever more sophisticated conceptual weaponry. In recent years, an enactive generalization of predictive processing – known as active inference – has been proposed as a unifying theory of brain functions…Read more
  •  143
    Keeping the collectivity in mind?
    with Harry Collins and Jeff Shrager
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (3): 353-374. 2008.
    The key question in this three way debate is the role of the collectivity and of agency. Collins and Shrager debate whether cognitive psychology has, like the sociology of knowledge, always taken the mind to extend beyond the individual. They agree that irrespective of the history, socialization is key to understanding the mind and that this is compatible with Clark’s position; the novelty in Clark’s “extended mind” position appears to be the role of the material rather than the role of other mi…Read more
  •  143
    What Reaching Teaches: Consciousness, Control, and the Inner Zombie
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (3): 563-594. 2007.
    What is the role of conscious visual experience in the control and guidance of human behaviour? According to some recent treatments, the role is surprisingly indirect. Conscious visual experience, on these accounts, serves the formation of plans and the selection of action types and targets, while the control of 'online' visually guided action proceeds via a quasi-independent non-conscious route. In response to such claims, critics such as (Wallhagen [2007], pp. 539-61) have suggested that the n…Read more
  •  606
    Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (3): 181-204. 2013.
    Brains, it has recently been argued, are essentially prediction machines. They are bundles of cells that support perception and action by constantly attempting to match incoming sensory inputs with top-down expectations or predictions. This is achieved using a hierarchical generative model that aims to minimize prediction error within a bidirectional cascade of cortical processing. Such accounts offer a unifying model of perception and action, illuminate the functional role of attention, and may…Read more
  •  12
    What is the significance of cross-national variability in sociosexuality?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (2): 280-280. 2005.
    Schmitt finds that national sex ratios predict levels of sociosexuality, but how we should interpret this result is unclear for both methodological and conceptual reasons. We criticize aspects of Schmitt's theorizing and his analytic strategy, and suggest that some additional analyses of the data in hand might be illuminating.
  •  196
    What ‘Extended Me’ knows
    Synthese 192 (11): 3757-3775. 2015.
    Arguments for the ‘extended mind’ seem to suggest the possibility of ‘extended knowers’—agents whose specifically epistemic virtues may depend on systems whose boundaries are not those of the brain or the biological organism. Recent discussions of this possibility invoke insights from virtue epistemology, according to which knowledge is the result of the application of some kind of cognitive skill or ability on the part of the agent. In this paper, I argue that there is a fundamental tension in …Read more
  •  41
    Connectionist Minds
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90 (1): 83-102. 1990.
    Andy Clark; VI*—Connectionist Minds, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 90, Issue 1, 1 June 1990, Pages 83–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelia.
  •  667
    Visual experience and motor action: Are the bonds too tight?
    Philosophical Review 110 (4): 495-519. 2001.
    How should we characterize the functional role of conscious visual experience? In particular, how do the conscious contents of visual experience guide, bear upon, or otherwise inform our ongoing motor activities? According to an intuitive and (I shall argue) philosophically influential conception, the links are often quite direct. The contents of conscious visual experience, according to this conception, are typically active in the control and guidance of our fine-tuned, real-time engagements wi…Read more