•  9
    Much Ado About Cognition: Critical Notice
    Mind 119 (476): 1047-1066. 2010.
  •  148
    Parallel distributed processing is transforming the field of cognitive science. Microcognition provides a clear, readable guide to this emerging paradigm from a cognitive philosopher's point of view. It explains and explores the biological basis of PDP, its psychological importance, and its philosophical relevance.
  •  380
    Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche
    Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10 (8): 370-374. 2006.
    Embodied agents use bodily actions and environmental interventions to make the world a better place to think in. Where does language fit into this emerging picture of the embodied, ecologically efficient agent? One useful way to approach this question is to consider language itself as a cognition-enhancing animal-built structure. To take this perspective is to view language as a kind of self-constructed cognitive niche: a persisting though never stationary material scaffolding whose critical rol…Read more
  •  6
    Linguistic anchors in the sea of thought?
    Pragmatics and Cognition 4 (1): 93-103. 1995.
    Language, according to Jackendoff, is more than just an instrument of communication and cultural transmission. It is also a tool which helps us to think. It does so, he suggests, by expanding the range of our conscious contents and hence allowing processes of attention and reflection to focus on items which would not otherwise be available for scrutiny. I applaud Jackendoff s basic vision, but raise some doubts concerning the argument. In particular, I wonder what it is about public language tha…Read more
  •  13
    In Memoriam: Susan Hurley
    In Lawrence Weiskrantz & Martin Davies (eds.), Frontiers of consciousness, Oxford University Press. pp. 2008. 2008.
  •  43
    I am John's brain
    Think 7 (19): 103-111. 2006.
    A talking brain corrects a few preconceptions.
  •  113
    Intentionality and information
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (3): 335-341. 1987.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  262
    Finding the Mind Content Type Journal Article DOI 10.1007/s11098-010-9598-9 Authors Andy Clark, Philosophy, University of Edinburgh, Dugald Stewart Building, 3 Charles Street, Edinburgh, EH8 9AD Scotland, UK Journal Philosophical Studies Online ISSN 1573-0883 Print ISSN 0031-8116.
  •  152
    From folk psychology to naive psychology
    Cognitive Science 11 (2): 139-54. 1987.
    The notion of folk‐psychology as a primitive speculative theory of the mental is called into question. There is cause to believe that folk‐psychology has more in common with a naive physics than with early speculative physical theorising. The distinction between these is elaborated. The conclusion drawn is that commonsense ascription of psychological content, though not a suitable finishing point for cognitive science, should still provide a more reliable source of data than some contemporary th…Read more
  •  28
    Erratum to: What ‘Extended Me’ knows
    Synthese 193 (1): 315-315. 2016.
  •  49
    How do intelligent agents spawn and exploit integrated processing regimes spanning brain, body, and world? The answer may lie in the ability of the biological brain to select actions and policies in the light of counterfactual predictions – predictions about what kinds of futures will result if such-and-such actions are launched. Appeals to the minimization of ‘counterfactual prediction errors’ (the ones that would result under various scenarios) already play a leading role in attempts to apply …Read more
  •  56
    Experiential facts?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2): 207-208. 1992.
  •  1087
    An embodied cognitive science?
    Trends in Cognitive Sciences 3 (9): 345-351. 1999.
    The last ten years have seen an increasing interest, within cognitive science, in issues concerning the physical body, the local environment, and the complex interplay between neural systems and the wider world in which they function. --œPhysically embodied, environmentally embedded--� approaches thus loom large on the contemporary cognitive scientific scene. Yet many unanswered questions remain, and the shape of a genuinely embodied, embedded science of the mind is still unclear. I begin by ske…Read more
  •  112
    Extended cognition and epistemology
    Philosophical Explorations 15 (2). 2012.
    Philosophical Explorations, Volume 15, Issue 2, Page 87-90, June 2012
  •  3
    Explaining Behaviour
    Philosophical Quarterly 40 (58): 95. 1990.
  •  24
    Embodiment and the Philosophy of Mind
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 43 35-51. 1998.
    Cognitive science is in some sense the science of the mind. But an increasingly influential theme, in recent years, has been the role of the physical body, and of the local environment, in promoting adaptive success. No right-minded cognitive scientist, to be sure, ever claimed that body and world were completely irrelevant to the understanding of mind. But there was, nonetheless, an unmistakeable tendency to marginalize such factors: to dwell on inner complexity whilst simplifying or ignoring t…Read more
  •  462
    Embodiment and the philosophy of mind
    In Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, Cambridge University Press. pp. 35-51. 1998.
    Cambridge University Press:1998) P. 35-52. To be reprinted in Alberto Peruzzi (ed) MIND
  •  44
    Experience and agency: Slipping the mesh
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 502-503. 2007.
    Can we really make sense of the idea (implied by Block's treatment) that there can be isolated islets of experience that are not even potentially available as fodder for a creature's conscious choices and decisions? The links between experience and the availability of information to guide conscious choice and inform reasoned action may be deeper than the considerations concerning (mere) reportability suggest
  •  291
    Does the material basis of conscious experience extend beyond the boundaries of the brain and central nervous system? In Clark 2009 I reviewed a number of ‘enactivist’ arguments for such a view and found none of them compelling. Ward (2012) rejects my analysis on the grounds that the enactivist deploys an essentially world-involving concept of experience that transforms the argumentative landscape in a way that makes the enactivist conclusion inescapable. I present an alternative (prediction-and…Read more
  •  580
    Doing without representing?
    Synthese 101 (3): 401-31. 1994.
      Connectionism and classicism, it generally appears, have at least this much in common: both place some notion of internal representation at the heart of a scientific study of mind. In recent years, however, a much more radical view has gained increasing popularity. This view calls into question the commitment to internal representation itself. More strikingly still, this new wave of anti-representationalism is rooted not in armchair theorizing but in practical attempts to model and understand …Read more
  •  69
    Connectionist minds
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90 83-102. 1990.
    Andy Clark; VI*—Connectionist Minds, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 90, Issue 1, 1 June 1990, Pages 83–102, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelia.
  •  17
    Cognitive incrementalism: The big issue
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (4): 536-537. 2000.
    Neural organization raises, in an especially clear way, a major problem confronting contemporary cognitive science. The problem (the “big issue” of my title) is: What is the relation between the strategies used to solve basic problems of perception and action and those used to solve more abstract or “cognitive” problems? Is there a smooth, incremental route from what Arbib et al. call “instinctual schemas” to higher-level kinds of cognitive prowess? I argue that, despite some suggestive comments…Read more
  •  234
    Adams and Aizawa, in a series of recent and forthcoming papers,, ) seek to refute, or perhaps merely to terminally embarrass, the friends of the extended mind. One such paper begins with the following illustration: "Question: Why did the pencil think that 2+2=4? Clark's Answer: Because it was coupled to the mathematician" Adams and Aizawa ms p.1 "That" the authors continue "about sums up what is wrong with Clark's extended mind hypothesis". The example of the pencil, they suggest, is just an esp…Read more
  •  261
    Consciousness as Generative Entanglement
    Journal of Philosophy 116 (12): 645-662. 2019.
    Recent work in cognitive and computational neuroscience depicts the human brain as a complex, multi-layer prediction engine. This family of models has had great success in accounting for a wide variety of phenomena involving perception, action, and attention. But despite their clear promise as accounts of the neurocomputational origins of perceptual experience, they have not yet been leveraged so as to shed light on the so-called “hard problem” of consciousness—the problem of explaining why and …Read more