•  160
    Neuroethics: Challenges for the 21st Century
    Cambridge University Press. 2007.
    Neuroscience has dramatically increased understanding of how mental states and processes are realized by the brain, thus opening doors for treating the multitude of ways in which minds become dysfunctional. This book explores questions such as when is it permissible to alter a person's memories, influence personality traits or read minds? What can neuroscience tell us about free will, self-control, self-deception and the foundations of morality? The view of neuroethics offered here argues that m…Read more
  •  23
    What Difference Does Consciousness Make?
    Monash Bioethics Review 28 (2): 13-25. 2009.
    The question whether and when it is morally appropriate to withdraw life-support from patients diagnosed as being in the persistent vegetative state is one of the most controversial in bioethics. Recent work on the neuroscience of consciousness seems to promise fundamentally to alter the debate, by demonstrating that some entirely unresponsive patients are in fact conscious. In this paper, I argue that though this work is extremely important scientifically, it ought to alter the debate over the …Read more
  •  111
    Culpable Ignorance
    Journal of Philosophical Research 41 263-271. 2016.
  •  180
    The Value of Consciousness
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 21 (1-2): 127-138. 2014.
    Consciousness, or its lack, is often invoked in debates in applied and normative ethics. Conscious beings are typically held to be significantly more morally valuable than non-consious, so that establishing whether a being is conscious becomes of critical importance. In this paper, I argue that the supposition that phenomenal consciousness explains the value of our experiences or our lives, and the moral value of beings who are conscious, is less well-grounded than is commonly thought. A great d…Read more
  • Terry Eagleton, The Idea of Culture (review)
    Philosophy in Review 22 28-30. 2002.
  •  108
    This book brings cutting edge neuroscience and psychology into dialogue with philosophical reflection to illuminate the loss of control experienced by addicts, and thereby cast light on ordinary agency and the way in which it sometimes goes wrong
  •  26
    George Graham, The Abraham Dilemma: A Divine Delusion. Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 36 (1): 11-13. 2016.
  • Stephen Cohen The Nature of Moral Reasoning (review)
    with Howard Harris
    Australian Journal of Professional and Applied Ethics 6 (1). 2004.
  •  86
    Zimmerman’s The Immorality of Punishment: A Critical Essay (review)
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (1): 103-112. 2015.
    In “The Immorality of Punishment”, Michael Zimmerman attempts to show that punishment is morally unjustified and therefore wrong. In this response, I focus on two main questions. First, I examine whether Zimmerman’s empirical claims—concerning our inability to identify wrongdoers who satisfy conditions on blameworthiness and who might be reformed through punishment, and the comparative efficacy of punitive and non-punitive responses to crime—stand up to scrutiny. Second, I argue that his crucial…Read more
  •  238
    Epistemic Akrasia and the Subsumption of Evidence: A Reconsideration
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 4 (1): 149-156. 2004.
    According to one influential view, advanced by Jonathan Adler, David Owens and Susan Hurley, epistemic akrasia is impossible because when we form a full belief, any apparent evidence against that belief loses its power over us. Thus theoretical reasoning is quite unlike practical reasoning, in that in the latter our desires continue to exert a pull, even when they are outweighed by countervailing considerations. I call this argument against the possibility of epistemic akrasia the subsumption vi…Read more
  •  126
    Does phenomenology overflow access?
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 15 (7): 29-38. 2008.
    Ned Block has influentially distinguished two kinds of consciousness, access and phenomenal consciousness. He argues that these two kinds of consciousness can dissociate, and therefore we cannot rely upon subjective report in constructing a science of consciousness. I argue that none of Block's evidence better supports his claim than the rival view, that access and phenomenal consciousness are perfectly correlated. Since Block's view is counterintuitive, and has wildly implausible implications, …Read more
  •  4
    Morality on the brain (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 108-109. 2011.
  •  311
    Virtual child pornography: The eroticization of inequality
    Ethics and Information Technology 4 (4): 319-323. 2002.
    The United States Supreme Court hasrecently ruled that virtual child pornographyis protected free speech, partly on the groundsthat virtual pornography does not harm actualchildren. I review the evidence for thecontention that virtual pornography might harmchildren, and find that it is, at best,inconclusive. Saying that virtual childpornography does not harm actual children isnot to say that it is completely harmless,however. Child pornography, actual or virtual,necessarily eroticizes inequality…Read more
  •  148
    Culture by nature
    Philosophical Explorations 14 (3): 237-248. 2011.
    One of the major conflicts in the social sciences since the Second World War has concerned whether, and to what extent, human beings have a nature. One view, traditionally associated with the political left, has rejected the notion that we have a contentful nature, and hoped thereby to underwrite the possibility that we can shape social institutions by references only to norms of justice, rather than our innate dispositions. This view has been in rapid retreat over the past three decades, in the…Read more
  •  34
    There May Be Costs to Failing to Enhance, as Well as to Enhancing
    American Journal of Bioethics 13 (7): 38-39. 2013.
    No abstract
  •  155
    The apology paradox and the non-identity problem
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208): 358-368. 2002.
    Janna Thompson has outlined ‘the apology paradox’, which arises whenever people apologize for an action or event upon which their existence is causally dependent. She argues that a sincere apology seems to entail a wish that the action or event had not occurred, but that we cannot sincerely wish that events upon which our existence depends had not occurred. I argue that Thompson’s paradox is a backward-looking version of Parfit’s (forward-looking) ‘non-identity problem’, where backward- and forwa…Read more
  •  5
    Springer Handbook of Neuroethics (edited book)
    with Jens Clausen
    Dordrecht. 2014.
  •  168
      Proponents of evolutionary psychology take the existence of humanuniversals to constitute decisive evidence in favor of their view. Ifthe same social norms are found in culture after culture, we have goodreason to believe that they are innate, they argue. In this paper Ipropose an alternative explanation for the existence of humanuniversals, which does not depend on them being the product of inbuiltpsychological adaptations. Following the work of Brian Skyrms, I suggestthat if a particular con…Read more
  •  28
    Respecting rights … to death
    Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (10): 608-611. 2006.
    Ravelingien et al1 argue that, given the restrictions that must be imposed on recipients of xenotransplanted organs, we should conduct clinical trials of xenotransplantation only on patients in a persistent vegetative state. I argue that there is no ethical barrier to using terminally ill patients instead. Such patients can choose to waive their rights to the liberties that xenotransplantation would probably restrict; it is surely rational to prefer to waive your rights rather than to die, and p…Read more
  •  22
    Editorial
    Neuroethics 1 (2): 73-74. 2008.
  •  2
    Neuromarketing: Ethical and Political Challenges
    Etica E Politica 11 (2): 10-17. 2009.
    Ethicists and ordinary people are typically more worried by interventions that alter agents’ mind by directly altering their brains than interventions than are focused on the environment, and thereby indirectly change minds. I argue that the causal route to changing minds is not itself important. Moreover, some of the most powerful techniques whereby behavior is altered without the consent or knowledge of agents involve environmental manipulations: manipulations of social space, for the benefit …Read more
  •  27
    What evolves when morality evolves?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (3): 612-620. 2006.
  • Michel Foucault
    Foucault Studies 20-31. 2004.
    ABSTRACT: In his last two books and in the essays and interviews associated with them, Foucault develops a new mode of ethical thought he describes as an aesthetics of existence. I argue that this new ethics bears a striking resemblance to the virtue ethics that has become prominent in Anglo‐American moral philosophy over the past three decades, in its classical sources, in its opposition to rule‐based systems and its positive emphasis upon what Foucault called the care for the self. I suggest t…Read more
  •  82
    The wisdom of the pack
    Philosophical Explorations 9 (1). 2006.
    This short article is a reply to Fine's criticisms of Haidt's social intuitionist model of moral judgement. After situating Haidt in the landscape of meta-ethical views, I examine Fine's argument, against Haidt, that the processes which give rise to moral judgements are amenable to rational control: first-order moral judgements, which are automatic, can nevertheless deliberately be brought to reflect higher-order judgements. However, Haidt's claims about the arationality of moral judgements seem…Read more