•  9
    Editorial
    Neuroethics 2 (1): 1-2. 2009.
  •  151
    Moore on Twin Earth
    Erkenntnis 75 (1): 137-146. 2011.
    In a series of articles, Terry Horgan and Mark Timmons have argued that Richard Boyd’s defence of moral realism, utilizing a causal theory of reference, fails. Horgan and Timmons construct a twin Earth-style thought experiment which, they claim, generates intuitions inconsistent with the realist account. In their thought experiment, the use of (allegedly) moral terms at a world is causally regulated by some property distinct from that regulating their use here on Earth; nevertheless, Horgan and …Read more
  •  82
    The wisdom of the pack
    Philosophical Explorations 9 (1). 2006.
    This short article is a reply to Fine's criticisms of Haidt's social intuitionist model of moral judgement. After situating Haidt in the landscape of meta-ethical views, I examine Fine's argument, against Haidt, that the processes which give rise to moral judgements are amenable to rational control: first-order moral judgements, which are automatic, can nevertheless deliberately be brought to reflect higher-order judgements. However, Haidt's claims about the arationality of moral judgements seem…Read more
  •  59
    Conspiracy Theories (review)
    Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 24 (1-2): 47-48. 2004.
  •  26
  •  32
  •  192
    Consciousness and Moral Responsibility
    Oxford University Press. 2014.
    Neil Levy presents a new theory of freedom and responsibility. He defends a particular account of consciousness--the global workspace view--and argues that consciousness plays an especially important role in action. There are good reasons to think that the naïve assumption, that consciousness is needed for moral responsibility, is in fact true
  •  8
    Self-Ownership
    Social Theory and Practice 28 (1): 77-99. 2002.
  •  98
    Cases in which we find ourselves irrationally worried about whether we have done something we habitually do are familiar to most people, but they have received surprisingly little attention in the philosophical literature. In this paper, I argue that available accounts designed to explain superficially similar mismatches between agents’ behavior and their beliefs fail to explain these cases. In the kinds of cases which have served as paradigms for extant accounts, contents are poised to drive be…Read more
  •  86
    Deafness, culture, and choice
    Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (5): 284-285. 2002.
    We should react to deaf parents who choose to have a deaf child with compassion not condemnationThere has been a great deal of discussion during the past few years of the potential biotechnology offers to us to choose to have only perfect babies, and of the implications that might have, for instance for the disabled. What few people foresaw is that these same technologies could be deliberately used to ensure that children would be born with disabilities. That this is a real possibility, and not …Read more
  •  151
    Neuroethics and the extended mind
    In Judy Illes & Barbara J. Sahakian (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Neuroethics, Oxford University Press. pp. 285. 2011.
    Neuroethics offers unprecedented opportunities as well as challenges. The challenges stem from the range of difficult ethical issues, which are confronted by neuroethicists. Issues concerning the nature of consciousness, of personal identity, free will, and so on, are all grist for the neuroethical mill. This article argues that this debate bears centrally on neuroethics and is significant for neuroethics. Whether the best interpretation of the facts to which proponents of the extended mind appe…Read more
  •  36
    Virtues Have Deeply Cultural Roots
    Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 14 (2): 195-202. 2015.
    8 page
  •  30
    Defending the Consciousness Thesis: A response to Robichaud, Sripada and Caruso
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 22 (7-8): 61-76. 2015.
    16 page
  •  2
    The presumption against direct manipulation
    Neuroethics: Challenges for the 21st Century. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. forthcoming.
  •  260
    Implicit Bias and Moral Responsibility: Probing the Data
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (3): 3-26. 2016.
  •  23
    The best of all possible paternalisms?
    Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (5): 304-305. 2014.
    I am grateful to the commentators, for their kind words and for their probing challenges. They range in the views they express, from those who seem to think I have not gone far enough in questioning the value of autonomy to those who think I have not challenged it at all. Given this diversity, it seems best to address their remarks sequentially.J D Trout is sympathetic to my project, and highlights his own work which supports it.1 Indeed, Trout's work—together with Michael Bishop and his own sta…Read more
  •  613
    Analytic and continental philosophy: Explaining the differences
    Metaphilosophy 34 (3): 284-304. 2003.
    A number of writers have tackled the task of characterizing the differences between analytic and Continental philosophy.I suggest that these attempts have indeed captured the most important divergences between the two styles but have left the explanation of the differences mysterious.I argue that analytic philosophy is usefully seen as philosophy conducted within a paradigm, in Kuhn’s sense of the word, whereas Continental philosophy assumes much less in the way of shared presuppositions, proble…Read more
  •  7
    Sartre
    ONEWorld Publications. 2002.
    This introduction traces the philosophical achievements of a thinker sonfluential that his death in 1980 brought 50,000 people on to the streets ofaris. The account of Jean-Paul Sartre - writer, journalist and intellectualornerstone of the 20th century - stretches from his early existential phaseo his later Marxist beliefs. With coverage of such major contemporary issuess human liberty, sociobiology, the ethics of work, and the influence ofenetics on ideas of individual freedom, Neil Levy uses a…Read more
  •  163
    Foucault as Virtue Ethicist
    Foucault Studies 1 20-31. 2004.
    In his last two books and in the essays and interviews associated with them, Foucault develops a new mode of ethical thought he describes as an aesthetics of existence. I argue that this new ethics bears a striking resemblance to the virtue ethics that has become prominent in Anglo-American moral philosophy over the past three decades, in its classical sources, in its opposition to rule-based systems and its positive emphasis upon what Foucault called the care for the self. I suggest that seeing…Read more
  • On determinism and freedom (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 56 (223): 310-312. 2006.
  •  238
    Enhancing Authenticity
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 28 (3): 308-318. 2011.
    Some philosophers have criticized the use of psychopharmaceuticals on the grounds that even if these drugs enhance the person using them, they threaten their authenticity. Others have replied by pointing out that the conception of authenticity upon which this argument rests is contestable; on a rival conception, psychopharmaceuticals might be used to enhance our authenticity. Since, however, it is difficult to decide between these competing conceptions of authenticity, the debate seems to end in…Read more
  •  73
    Morality on the brain (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 (54): 108-109. 2011.
  •  20
    Untimely Meditations
    Symposium 2 (1): 61-75. 1998.
    Most accounts of recent French intellectual history are organized around a fundamental rupture, which divides thought and thinkers into two eras: ‘modern’ and ‘postmodern’. But the attempts to identify the features which characterise these eras seem, at best, inconclusive. In this paper, I examine this rupture, by way of a comparison of two thinkers representative of the divide. Sartre seems as uncontroversially modern (and therefore out of date) as any twentieth-century can be, while Foucault’s…Read more
  •  379
    Downshifting and meaning in life
    Ratio 18 (2). 2005.
    So-called downshifters seek more meaningful lives by decreasing the amount of time they devote to work, leaving more time for the valuable goods of friendship, family and personal development. But though these are indeed meaning-conferring activities, they do not have the right structure to count as superlatively meaningful. Only in work – of a certain kind – can superlative meaning be found. It is by active engagements in projects, which are activities of the right structure, dedicated to the a…Read more