Washington University in St. Louis
Philosophy/Neuroscience/Psychology Program
PhD, 1985
Lincoln, Nebraska, United States of America
  •  25
    Neurath’s Boat Will Take You Where You Want to Go: On Naturalized Epistemology and Historicism
    Journal of the Philosophy of History 6 (3): 389-414. 2012.
    Naturalized epistemology is not a recent invention, nor is it a philosophical invention. Rather, it is a cognitive phenomena that is pervasive and desirable in the way of human epistemic engagement with their world. It is a matter of the way that one’s cognitive processes can be modulated by information gotten from those same or wider cognitive processes. Such modulational control enhances the reliability of one’s cognitive processes in many ways ‐ and judgments about objective epistemic justifi…Read more
  •  37
    Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology (edited book)
    with John Greco
    Oxford University Press UK. 2015.
    Epistemic Evaluation aims to explore and apply a particular methodology in epistemology. The methodology is to consider the point or purpose of our epistemic evaluations, and to pursue epistemological theory in light of such matters. Call this purposeful epistemology. The idea is that considerations about the point and purpose of epistemic evaluation might fruitfully constrain epistemological theory and yield insights for epistemological reflection. Several contributions to this volume explicitl…Read more
  • The Role of the Empirical in Epistemology
    University of Memphis, Dept. Of Philosophy. 2000.
  •  58
    In codifying the methods of translation, several writers have formulated maxims that would constrain interpreters to construe their subjects as (more or less) rational speakers of the truth. Such maxims have come to be known as versions of the principle of charity. W. V. O. Quine suggests an empirical, not purely methodological, basis for his version of that principle. Recently, Stephen Stich has criticized Quine's attempt to found the principle of charity in translation on information about the…Read more
  •  190
    Transglobal evidentialism-reliabilism
    Acta Analytica 22 (4): 281-300. 2007.
    We propose an approach to epistemic justification that incorporates elements of both reliabilism and evidentialism, while also transforming these elements in significant ways. After briefly describing and motivating the non-standard version of reliabilism that Henderson and Horgan call “transglobal” reliabilism, we harness some of Henderson and Horgan’s conceptual machinery to provide a non-reliabilist account of propositional justification (i.e., evidential support). We then invoke this account…Read more
  •  29
    Relies to our critics
    Philosophical Studies 169 (3): 549-564. 2014.
    We respond to the central concerns raised by our commentators to our book, The Epistemological Spectrum. Casullo believes that our account of what we term “low-grade a priori” justification provides important clarification of a kind of philosophical reflection. However he objects to calling such reflection a priori. We explain what we think is at stake. Along the way, we comment on his idea of that there may be an epistemic payoff to making a distinction between assumptions and presumptions. In …Read more
  •  15
    On the Testability of Psychological Generalizations
    Philosophy of Science 58 (4): 586-606. 1991.
    Rosenberg argues that intentional generalizations in the human sciences cannot be law-like because they are not amenable to significant empirical refinement. This irrefinability is said to result from the principle that supposedly controls in intentional explanation also serving as the standard for successful interpretation. The only credible evidence bearing on such a principle would then need conform to it. I argue that psychological generalizations are refinable and can be nomic. I show how e…Read more
  •  51
    Interpretation and Explanation in the Human Sciences
    State University of New York Press. 1993.
    Refutes the methodological separatists who hold that the logic of explanation and testing in the human sciences is fundamentally different than in the natural sciences, and develops complementary accounts for interpretation and explanation, ...
  •  219
    Monitoring and Anti-Reductionism in the Epistemology of Testimony
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (3). 2006.
    One of the central points of contention in the epistemology of testimony concerns the uniqueness (or not) of the justification of beliefs formed through testimony--whether such justification can be accounted for in terms of, or 'reduced to,' other familiar sort of justification, e.g. without relying on any epistemic principles unique to testimony. One influential argument for the reductionist position, found in the work of Elizabeth Fricker, argues by appeal to the need for the hearer to monitor…Read more
  •  46
    Comments on Rosenberg's Paper
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 34 (S1): 205-216. 1996.
  •  45
    Transglobal Reliabilism
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 6 (2): 171-195. 2006.
    We here propose an account of what it is for an agent to be objectively justified in holding some belief. We present in outline this approach, which we call transglobal reliabilism, and we discuss how it is motivated by various thought experiments. While transglobal reliabilism is an externalist epistemology, we think that it accommodates traditional internalist concerns and objections in a uniquely natural and respectful way.
  •  66
    Epistemic competence
    Philosophical Papers 23 (3): 139-167. 1994.
    No abstract
  •  79
    Norms, normative principles, and explanation: On not getting is from ought
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (3): 329-364. 2002.
    It seems that hope springs eternal for the cherished idea that norms (or normativeprinciples) explain actions or regularities in actions. But it also seems thatthere are many ways of going wrong when taking norms and normative principlesas explanatory. The author argues that neither norms nor normative principles—insofar as they are the sort of things with normative force—is explanatoryof what is done. He considers the matter using both erotetic and ontic models ofexplanation. He further conside…Read more