• University of Cologne
    Department of Philosophy
    CONCEPT - Cologne Center for Contemporary Epistemology and the Kantian Tradition
    Junior Professor
University of Connecticut
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 2013
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology
  •  1467
    The Composite Nature of Epistemic Justification
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (1). 2017.
    According to many, to have epistemic justification to believe P is just for it to be epistemically permissible to believe P. Others think it is for believing P to be epistemically good. Yet others think it has to do with being epistemically blameless in believing P. All such views of justification encounter problems. Here, a new view of justification is proposed according to which justification is a kind of composite normative status. The result is a view of justification that offers hope of sol…Read more
  •  1777
    How To Be Conservative: A Partial Defense of Epistemic Conservatism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (3): 501-514. 2013.
    Conservatism about perceptual justification tells us that we cannot have perceptual justification to believe p unless we also have justification to believe that perceptual experiences are reliable. There are many ways to maintain this thesis, ways that have not been sufficiently appreciated. Most of these ways lead to at least one of two problems. The first is an over-intellectualization problem, whereas the second problem concerns the satisfaction of the epistemic basing requirement on justifie…Read more
  •  375
    Etiological information and diminishing justification
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 61 (2): 1-25. 2018.
    Sometimes it’s reasonable to reduce confidence in a proposition in response to gaining etiological information. Suppose, for example, a theist learns that her theism is ‘due to’ her religious upbringing. There is a clear range of cases where it would be reasonable for her to respond by slightly decreasing her confidence in God’s existence. So long as reasonability and justification are distinct, this reasonability claim would appear consistent with the thesis that this kind of etiological inform…Read more
  •  619
    Why Worry about Epistemic Circularity?
    Journal of Philosophical Research 41 (9999): 33-52. 2016.
    Although Alston believed epistemically circular arguments were able to justify their conclusions, he was also disquieted by them. We will argue that Alston was right to be disquieted. We explain Alston’s view of epistemic circularity, the considerations that led him to accept it, and the purposes he thought epistemically circular arguments could serve. We then build on some of Alston’s remarks and introduce further limits to the usefulness of such arguments and introduce a new problem that stems…Read more
  •  612
    According to an orthodox account of the relationship between propositional and doxastic justification, basing one’s belief in P on one’s source of propositional justification to believe P suffices for having a doxastically justified belief. But in an increasingly recognized work Turri argues that this thesis fails and proposes a new view according to which having propositional justification depends on having the ability to acquire doxastic justification. Turri’s novel position has surprisingly f…Read more
  •  178
    How Doxastic Justification Helps Us Solve the Puzzle of Misleading Higher-Order Evidence
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (S1): 308-328. 2016.
    Certain plausible evidential requirements and coherence requirements on rationality seem to yield dilemmas of rationality (in a specific, objectionable sense) when put together with the possibility of misleading higher-order evidence. Epistemologists have often taken such dilemmas to be evidence that we’re working with some false principle. In what follows I show how one can jointly endorse an evidential requirement, a coherence requirement, and the possibility of misleading higher-order evidenc…Read more