•  30
    Environmental Ethics
    Philosophy in the Contemporary World 8 (2): 15-26. 2001.
    This paper articulates a framework, “E,” for developing ethical claims about environmental issues. E is a general framework for constructing arguments and working out disputes, rather than a particular theory. It may be deployed in various ways by writers with quite different views to generate diverse arguments applying to a broad panoply of issues. E can serve as a common language between those who adopt anthropocentric and nonanthropocentric standpoints. E is anthropocentric in the sense that …Read more
  •  32
    Aristotelian matter, potentiality and quarks
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 17 (4): 507-521. 1979.
  •  173
    Why we are responsible for our emotions
    Mind 95 (377): 37-56. 1986.
    It is often said that one cannot be held responsible for something one cannot help. Indeed, Ted Honderich, Paul Edwards, and C. A. Campbell have suggested that it is obtuse, barbaric, or a solecism to think otherwise 1. Thus, if (contra Sartre and others) one cannot help feeling one's emotions, one is not responsible for one's emotions. In this paper I will argue otherwise; one is responsible for one's emotions, even if one cannot help feeling them. 2 In particular, I will define a rather specia…Read more
  •  23
    Technology and civil disobedience: Why engineers have a special duty to obey the law
    Science and Engineering Ethics 1 (2): 163-168. 1995.
    Engineers have a greater responsibility than many other professionals not to commit civil disobedience in performing their jobs as engineers. It does not follow that engineers have no responsibility for their company’s actions. Morally, engineer may be required to speak out within the company or even publicly against her company. An engineer may be required to work on a project or quit her job. None of these acts, generally, are against the law. An engineer may be morally required to commit civi…Read more