•  20
    Yablo’s Paradox and Russellian Propositions
    Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 28 (2): 127-142. 2008.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:January 22, 2009 (8:41 pm) G:\WPData\TYPE2802\russell 28,2 048red.wpd russell: the Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies n.s. 28 (winter 2008–09): 127–42 The Bertrand Russell Research Centre, McMaster U. issn 0036-01631; online 1913-8032 YABLO’S PARADOX AND RUSSELLIAN PROPOSITIONS Gregory Landini Philosophy / U. of Iowa Iowa City, ia 52242–1408, usa [email protected] Is self-reference necessary for the production of Liar parado…Read more
  •  38
    Typos of Principia Mathematica
    History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (4). 2013.
    Principia Mathematic goes to great lengths to hide its order/type indices and to make it appear as if its incomplete symbols behave as if they are singular terms. But well-hidden as they are, we cannot understand the proofs in Principia unless we bring them into focus. When we do, some rather surprising results emerge ? which is the subject of this paper
  •  95
    Frege’s Cardinals as Concept-correlates
    Erkenntnis 65 (2): 207-243. 2006.
    In his "Grundgesetze", Frege hints that prior to his theory that cardinal numbers are objects he had an "almost completed" manuscript on cardinals. Taking this early theory to have been an account of cardinals as second-level functions, this paper works out the significance of the fact that Frege's cardinal numbers is a theory of concept-correlates. Frege held that, where n > 2, there is a one—one correlation between each n-level function and an n—1 level function, and a one—one correlation betw…Read more
  •  11
    7 Russell's Substitutional Theory
    In Nicholas Griffin (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell, Cambridge University Press. pp. 241. 2003.
  •  39
    Russell's substitutional theory of classes and relations
    History and Philosophy of Logic 8 (2): 171-200. 1987.
    This paper examines Russell's substitutional theory of classes and relations, and its influence on the development of the theory of logical types between the years 1906 and the publication of Principia Mathematica (volume I) in 1910. The substitutional theory proves to have been much more influential on Russell's writings than has been hitherto thought. After a brief introduction, the paper traces Russell's published works on type-theory up to Principia. Each is interpreted as presenting a versi…Read more
  •  34
    New Evidence concerning Russell's Substitutional Theory of Classes
    Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 9 (1): 26. 1989.
  •  90
    Wittgenstein's notes on logic – Michael Potter (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 60 (240): 645-648. 2010.
    No Abstract
  •  57
    How to Russell Another Meinongian
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 37 (1): 93-122. 1990.
    This article compares the theory of Meinongian objects proposed by Edward Zalta with a theory of fiction formulated within an early Russellian framework. The Russellian framework is the second-order intensional logic proposed by Nino B. Cocchiarelly as a reconstruction of the form of Logicism Russell was examining shortly after writing The Principles of Mathematics. A Russellian theory of denoting concepts is developed in this intensional logic and applied as a theory of the "objects' of fiction…Read more
  •  34
    For logicians and metaphysicians curious about the evolution of Russell's logic from The Principles of Mathematics to Principia Mathematica, no volume of the Collected Papers of Bertr...
  •  39
    Quantification Theory in *8 of Principia Mathematica and the Empty Domain
    History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (1): 47-59. 2005.
    The second printing of Principia Mathematica in 1925 offered Russell an occasion to assess some criticisms of the Principia and make some suggestions for possible improvements. In Appendix A, Russell offered *8 as a new quantification theory to replace *9 of the original text. As Russell explained in the new introduction to the second edition, the system of *8 sets out quantification theory without free variables. Unfortunately, the system has not been well understood. This paper shows that Russ…Read more
  •  42
    Russell
    Routledge. 2011.
    Landini discusses the second edition of Principia Mathematica, to show Russella (TM)s intellectual relationship with Wittgenstein and Ramsey.
  •  143
    Zermelo and Russell's Paradox: Is There a Universal set?
    Philosophia Mathematica 21 (2): 180-199. 2013.
    Zermelo once wrote that he had anticipated Russell's contradiction of the set of all sets that are not members of themselves. Is this sufficient for having anticipated Russell's Paradox — the paradox that revealed the untenability of the logical notion of a set as an extension? This paper argues that it is not sufficient and offers criteria that are necessary and sufficient for having discovered Russell's Paradox. It is shown that there is ample evidence that Russell satisfied the criteria and t…Read more
  •  18
    Logicism without Peano 4
    Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies 16. 2007.
  •  58
  •  94
    Frege's Cardinals Do Not Always Obey Hume's Principle
    History and Philosophy of Logic 38 (2): 127-153. 2017.
    Hume's Principle, dear to neo-Logicists, maintains that equinumerosity is both necessary and sufficient for sameness of cardinal number. All the same, Whitehead demonstrated in Principia Mathematica's logic of relations that Cantor's power-class theorem entails that Hume's Principle admits of exceptions. Of course, Hume's Principle concerns cardinals and in Principia's ‘no-classes’ theory cardinals are not objects in Frege's sense. But this paper shows that the result applies as well to the theo…Read more
  •  34
    Russell's Separation of the Logical and Semantic Paradoxes
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 3 257-294. 2004.
  •  50
    Words Without Objects: Semantics, Ontology, and Logic for Non-Singularity
    History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (2): 204-208. 2009.
    HENRY LAYCOCK, Words Without Objects: Semantics, Ontology, and Logic for Non-Singularity. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006. xvi + 202pp. £35.00. ISBN 0‐19‐928171‐8. Gregory Landini, Department of Phil...
  •  38
    Review: D. Bostock. Russell’s Logical Atomism (review)
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 2 (1). 2013.
    This is review of D. David Bostock. Russell’s Logical Atomism
  •  68
    Decomposition and analysis in Frege’s Grundgesetze
    History and Philosophy of Logic 17 (1-2): 121-139. 1996.
    Frege seems to hold two incompatible theses:(i) that sentences differing in structure can yet express the same sense; and (ii) that the senses of the meaningful parts of a complex term are determinate parts of the sense of the term. Dummett offered a solution, distinguishing analysis from decomposition. The present paper offers an embellishment of Dummett?s distinction by providing a way of depicting the internal structures of complex senses?determinate structures that yield distinct decompositi…Read more
  •  62
    Ontology Made Easy By Amie L. Thomasson
    Analysis 77 (1): 243-246. 2017.
  • Wittgenstein reads Russell
    In Marie McGinn & Oskari Kuusela (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  44
    How to Russell Another Meinongian
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 37 (1): 93-122. 1990.
    This article compares the theory of Meinongian objects proposed by Edward Zalta with a theory of fiction formulated within an early Russellian framework. The Russellian framework is the second-order intensional logic proposed by Nino B. Cocchiarelly as a reconstruction of the form of Logicism Russell was examining shortly after writing The Principles of Mathematics. A Russellian theory of denoting concepts is developed in this intensional logic and applied as a theory of the "objects' of fiction…Read more
  •  96
    In his new introduction to the 1925 second edition of Principia Mathematica, Russell maintained that by adopting Wittgenstein's idea that a logically perfect language should be extensional mathematical induction could be rectified for finite cardinals without the axiom of reducibility. In an Appendix B, Russell set forth a proof. Godel caught a defect in the proof at *89.16, so that the matter of rectification remained open. Myhill later arrived at a negative result: Principia with extensionalit…Read more
  •  56
    Erik C. Banks, The Realistic Empiricism of Mach, James and Russell (review)
    Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 6 (2): 329-333. 2016.