•  72
    The Legitimacy of Placebo Treatments in Clinical Practice: Evidence and Ethics
    with Luana Colloca
    American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12): 39-47. 2009.
    Physicians commonly recommend ?placebo treatments?, which are not believed to have specific efficacy for the patient's condition. Motivations for placebo treatments include complying with patient expectations and promoting a placebo effect. In this article, we focus on two key empirical questions that must be addressed in order to assess the ethical legitimacy of placebo treatments in clinical practice: 1) do placebo treatments have the potential to produce clinically significant benefit? and 2)…Read more
  •  71
    Clinical obligations and public health programmes: healthcare provider reasoning about managing the incidental results of newborn screening
    with R. Z. Hayeems, Y. Bombard, J. Little, J. C. Carroll, B. Wilson, J. Allanson, M. Paynter, J. P. Bytautas, R. Christensen, and P. Chakraborty
    Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (10): 626-634. 2009.
    Background: Expanded newborn screening generates incidental results, notably carrier results. Yet newborn screening programmes typically restrict parental choice regarding receipt of this non-health serving genetic information. Healthcare providers play a key role in educating families or caring for screened infants and have strong beliefs about the management of incidental results. Methods: To inform policy on disclosure of infant sickle cell disorder (SCD) carrier results, a mixed-methods stud…Read more
  •  68
    Rethinking the Ethics of Vital Organ Donations
    with Robert D. Truog
    Hastings Center Report 38 (6): 38-46. 2008.
    Accepted medical practice already violates the dead donor rule. Explicitly jettisoning the rule—allowing vital organs to be extracted, under certain conditions, from living patients—is a radical change only at the conceptual level. But it would expand the pools of eligible organ donors.
  •  68
    Death and legal fictions
    with S. K. Shah and R. D. Truog
    Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (12): 719-722. 2011.
    Advances in life-saving technologies in the past few decades have challenged our traditional understandings of death. Traditionally, death was understood to occur when a person stops breathing, their heart stops beating and they are cold to the touch. Today, physicians determine death by relying on a diagnosis of ‘total brain failure’ or by waiting a short while after circulation stops. Evidence has emerged, however, that the conceptual bases for these approaches to determining death are fundame…Read more
  •  65
    When and Why Is Research without Consent Permissible?
    Hastings Center Report 46 (2): 35-43. 2016.
    The view that research with competent adults requires valid consent to be ethical perhaps finds its clearest expression in the Nuremberg Code, whose famous first principle asserts that “the voluntary consent of the human subject is absolutely essential.” In a similar vein, the United Nations International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights states that “no one shall be subjected without his free consent to medical or scientific experimentation.” Yet although some formulations of the consent p…Read more
  •  63
    Brain death: justifications and critiques
    with Robert D. Truog
    Clinical Ethics 7 (3): 128-132. 2012.
    Controversies about the diagnosis and meaning of brain death have existed as long as the concept itself. Here we review the historical development of brain death, and then evaluate the various attempts to justify the claim that patients who are diagnosed as brain dead can be considered dead for all legal and social purposes, and especially with regard to procuring their vital organs for transplantation. While we agree with most commentators that death should be defined as the loss of integration…Read more
  •  63
    Assessing research risks systematically: the net risks test
    with D. Wendler
    Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (8): 481-486. 2007.
    Dual-track assessment directs research ethics committees to assess the risks of research interventions based on the unclear distinction between therapeutic and non-therapeutic interventions. The net risks test, in contrast, relies on the clinically familiar method of assessing the risks and benefits of interventions in comparison to the available alternatives and also focuses attention of the RECs on the central challenge of protecting research participants.Research guidelines around the world r…Read more
  •  62
    Nudging, Autonomy, and Valid Consent: Context Matters
    American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6): 12-13. 2013.
    No abstract
  •  62
    Placebo and Deception: A Commentary
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 40 (1): 69-82. 2015.
    In a recent article in this Journal, Shlomo Cohen and Haim Shapiro introduce the concept of “comparable placebo treatments” —placebo treatments with biological effects similar to the drugs they replace—and argue that doctors are not being deceptive when they prescribe or administer CPTs without revealing that they are placebos. We critique two of Cohen and Shapiro’s primary arguments. First, Cohen and Shapiro argue that offering undisclosed placebos is not lying to the patient, but rather is mak…Read more
  •  61
    Sham surgery: An ethical analysis
    Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (1): 157-166. 2004.
    Surgical clinical trials have seldom used a “sham” or placebo surgical procedure as a control, owing to ethical concerns. Recently, several ethical commentators have argued that sham surgery is either inherently or presumptively unethical. In this article I contend that these arguments are mistaken, and that there are no sound ethical reasons for an absolute prohibition of sham surgery in clinical trials. Reflecting on three cases of sham surgery, especially on the recently reported results of a…Read more
  •  57
    Phase 1 oncology trials and informed consent
    with Steven Joffe
    Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (12): 761-764. 2013.
    Ethical concerns have been raised about the quality of informed consent by participants in phase 1 oncology trials. Interview surveys indicate that substantial proportions of trial participants do not understand the purpose of these trials—evaluating toxicity and dosing for subsequent efficacy studies—and overestimate the prospect of therapeutic benefit that they offer. In this article we argue that although these data suggest the desirability of enhancing the process of information disclosure a…Read more
  •  57
    A Critique of Clinical Equipoise: Therapeutic Misconception in the Ethics of Clinical Trials
    with Howard Brody
    Hastings Center Report 33 (3): 19-28. 2003.
    A predominant ethical view holds that physician‐investigators should conduct their research with therapeutic intent. And since a physician offering a therapy wouldn't prescribe second‐rate treatments, the experimental intervention and the best proven therapy should appear equally effective. "Clinical equipoise" is necessary. But this perspective is flawed. The ethics of research and of therapy are fundamentally different, and clinical equipoise should be abandoned.
  •  57
    Steven Joffe and Franklin G. Miller reply
    with Steven Joffe
    Hastings Center Report 38 (5): 7-7. 2008.
  •  56
    Decapitation and the definition of death
    with R. D. Truog
    Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (10): 632-634. 2010.
    Although established in the law and current practice, the determination of death according to neurological criteria continues to be controversial. Some scholars have advocated return to the traditional circulatory and respiratory criteria for determining death because individuals diagnosed as ‘brain dead’ display an extensive range of integrated biological functioning with the aid of mechanical ventilation. Others have attempted to refute this stance by appealing to the analogy between decapitat…Read more
  •  56
    Evaluating the therapeutic misconception
    with Steven Joffe
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 16 (4): 353-366. 2006.
    : The "therapeutic misconception," described by Paul Appelbaum and colleagues more than 20 years ago, refers to the tendency of participants in clinical trials to confuse the design and conduct of research with personalized medical care. Although the "therapeutic misconception" has become a term of art in research ethics, little systematic attention has been devoted to the ethical significance of this phenomenon. This article examines critically the way in which Appelbaum and colleagues formulat…Read more
  •  54
    Changing the Conversation About Brain Death
    with Robert D. Truog
    American Journal of Bioethics 14 (8): 9-14. 2014.
    We seek to change the conversation about brain death by highlighting the distinction between brain death as a biological concept versus brain death as a legal status. The fact that brain death does not cohere with any biologically plausible definition of death has been known for decades. Nevertheless, this fact has not threatened the acceptance of brain death as a legal status that permits individuals to be treated as if they are dead. The similarities between “legally dead” and “legally blind” …Read more
  •  54
    Paul Litton and Franklin G. Miller Reply to Madeline M. Motta
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (4): 635-635. 2005.
  •  53
    The concept of medically indicated treatment
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 18 (1): 91-98. 1993.
    The following article examines critically Robert Veaten's argument that respect for patient autonomy invalidates the concept of medically indicated treatment. I contend that when judgments of medically indicated treatment are distinguished from what ought to be done in a given case, all things considered, they are compatible with patient autonomy. Yet there remains a significant danger, which needs to be guarded against, that physicians will use these judgments to dominate their interactions wit…Read more
  •  51
    Research on Medical Records Without Informed Consent
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (3): 560-566. 2008.
    Observational research involving access to personally identifiable data in medical records has often been conducted without informed consent, owing to practical barriers to soliciting consent and concerns about selection bias. Nevertheless, medical records research without informed consent appears to conflict with basic ethical norms relating to clinical research and personal privacy. This article analyzes the scope of these norms and provides an ethical justification for research using personal…Read more
  •  51
    When Scientists Deceive: Applying the Federal Regulations
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (2): 344-350. 2009.
    Deception is a useful methodological device for studying attitudes and behavior, but deceptive studies fail to fulfill the informed consent requirements in the U.S. federal regulations. This means that before they can be approved by Institutional Review Boards, they must satisfy the four regulatory conditions for a waiver or alteration of these requirements. To illustrate our interpretation, we apply the conditions to a recent study that used deception to show that subjects judged the same wine …Read more
  •  49
    Two Philosophical Deaths: Hume and Hitchens
    Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 56 (2): 251-258. 2013.
    What is a good death? How does one live well in the face of (potentially) terminal illness? Philosophical analysis has a great deal to offer in approaching these puzzling and deep questions. Perhaps more can be gleaned of cultural and personal significance, however, from narratives of those who have been forced to face these questions in their lives and in their writings. The greatest yield, I suggest, comes from combining narrative with philosophical reflections.Commentators have frequently con…Read more
  •  49
    This book challenges fundamental doctrines of established medical ethics. It is argued that the routine practice of stopping life support technology causes the death of patients and that donors of vital organs (hearts, liver, lungs, and both kidneys) are not really dead at the time that their organs are removed for life-saving transplantation. Although these practices are ethically legitimate, they are not compatible with traditional medical ethics: they conflict with the norms that doctors must…Read more
  •  47
    Professional Integrity and Physician‐Assisted Death
    with Howard Brody
    Hastings Center Report 25 (3): 8-17. 1995.
    The practice of voluntary physician‐assisted death as a last resort is compatible with doctors' duties to practice competently, to avoid harming patients unduly, to refrain from medical fraud, and to preserve patients' trust. It therefore does not violate physicians' professional integrity.
  •  47
    Can RESEARCH and CARE Be Ethically Integrated?
    with Emily A. Largent and Steven Joffe
    Hastings Center Report 41 (4): 37-46. 2011.
    Medical ethics assumes a clear boundary between clinical research and clinical medicine: one produces knowledge for the benefit of future patients, while the other provides optimal care to individuals right now. It also assumes that the two cannot be integrated without sacrificing the needs of the current patient to those of future patients. But integration could allow us to provide better care to everyone, now and in the future.
  •  46
    Drawing the line on physician-assisted death
    with Lynn A. Jansen and Steven Wall
    Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (3): 190-197. 2019.
    Drawing the line on physician assistance in physician-assisted death continues to be a contentious issue in many legal jurisdictions across the USA, Canada and Europe. PAD is a medical practice that occurs when physicians either prescribe or administer lethal medication to their patients. As more legal jurisdictions establish PAD for at least some class of patients, the question of the proper scope of this practice has become pressing. This paper presents an argument for restricting PAD to the t…Read more
  •  46
    Personal Care in Learning Health Care Systems
    with Scott Y. H. Kim
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 25 (4): 419-435. 2015.
    The “learning health care system” is being heralded as offering great potential for improving the quality and cost-worthiness of medical care by closely integrating the care of patients with the accumulation of aggregate data that can guide evidence-based medicine. By using electronic medical records, routine patient care and administrative data will be available for systematic observational studies. With the aid of these electronic medical records, quality-improvement studies of institutional p…Read more
  •  44
    The internal morality of medicine: Explication and application to managed care
    with Howard Brody
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 23 (4). 1998.
    Some ethical issues facing contemporary medicine cannot be fully understood without addressing medicine's internal morality. Medicine as a profession is characterized by certain moral goals and morally acceptable means for achieving those goals. The list of appropriate goals and means allows some medical actions to be classified as clear violations of the internal morality, and others as borderline or controversial cases. Replies are available for common objections, including the superfluity of …Read more
  •  44
    It Is Time to Abandon the Dogma That Brain Death Is Biological Death
    with Michael Nair-Collins and Robert D. Truog
    Hastings Center Report 51 (4): 18-21. 2021.
    Drawing on a recent case report of a pregnant, brain‐dead woman who gave birth to a healthy child after over seven months of intensive care treatment, this essay rejects the established doctrine in medicine that brain death constitutes the biological death of the human being. The essay describes three policy options with respect to determination of death and vital organ transplantation in the case of patients who are irreversibly comatose but remain biologically alive.
  •  44
    : Recent controversial decisions to terminate several large clinical trials have called attention to the need for developing a sound ethical framework to determine when trials should be stopped in light of emerging efficacy data. Currently, the fundamental rationale for stopping trials early is based on the principle that equipoise has been disturbed. We present an analysis of the ethical and practical problems with the "equipoise disturbed" position and describe an alternative ethical framework…Read more