•  9
    Transvaluationism: The Benign Logical Incoherence of Vagueness
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 14 (1): 20-35. 2006.
  •  115
    Causal Compatibilism and the Exclusion Problem
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 16 (1): 95-115. 2001.
    Causal compatibilism claims that even though physics is causally closed, and even though mental properties are multiply realizable and are not identical to physical causal properties, mental properties are causal properties nonetheless. This position asserts that there is genuine causation at multiple descriptive/ontological levels; physics-level causal claims are not really incompatible with mentalistic causal claims. I articulate and defend a version of causal compatibilism that incorporates t…Read more
  •  200
    Transvaluationism about vagueness: A progress report
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 48 (1): 67-94. 2010.
    The philosophical account of vagueness I call "transvaluationism" makes three fundamental claims. First, vagueness is logically incoherent in a certain way: it essentially involves mutually unsatisfiable requirements that govern vague language, vague thought-content, and putative vague objects and properties. Second, vagueness in language and thought (i.e., semantic vagueness) is a genuine phenomenon despite possessing this form of incoherence—and is viable, legitimate, and indeed indispensable.…Read more
  •  23
    Attitudinatives
    Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (2). 1989.
  •  30
    Replies to papers
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 63 (1): 302-340. 2002.
    Jaegwon Kim argues that one should distinguish naturalism from materialism, and that both should be construed as ontological rather than epistemological. I agree, on both counts. Although I have sometimes tended to slur together materialism and naturalism in of my writings (as is done in much recent philosophy), I do think that it is important to distinguish them. It is a serious philosophical task to get clearer about how each position is best articulated, and about ways that one could embrace …Read more
  •  3
    Editors' Introduction
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (S1). 2000.
  •  159
    Facing Up to the Sorites Paradox
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 6 99-111. 2000.
    The ancient sorites paradox has important implications for metaphysics, for logic, and for semantics. Metaphysically, the paradox can be harnessed to produce a powerful argument for the claim that there cannot be vague objects or vague properties. With respect to logic, the paradox forces a choice between the highly counterintuitive ‘epistemic’ account of vagueness and the rejection of classical two-valued logic. Regarding semantics, nonclassical approaches to the logic of vagueness lead natural…Read more
  •  26
    Editor's Introduction
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 33 (S1). 1995.
  •  43
  •  78
    Materialism: Matters Of Definition, Defense, and Deconstruction
    Philosophical Studies 131 (1): 157-183. 2006.
    How should the metaphysical hypothesis of materialism be formulated? What strategies look promising for defending this hypothesis? How good are the prospects for its successful defense, especially in light of the infamous "hard problem" of phenomenal consciousness? I will say something about each of these questions
  •  119
    Abundant truth in an austere world
    with Terry Horgan and Matjaž Potrč
    In Patrick Greenough & Michael P. Lynch (eds.), Truth and realism, Oxford University Press. pp. 137--167. 2006.
    What is real? Less than you might think. We advocate austere metaphysical realism---a form of metaphysical realism claiming that a correct ontological theory will repudiate numerous putative entities and properties that are posited in everyday thought and discourse, and also will even repudiate numerous putative objects and properties that are posited by well confirmed scientific theories. We have lately defended a specific version of austere metaphysical realism which asserts that there is real…Read more
  •  158
    I maintain, in defending “thirdism,” that Sleeping Beauty should do Bayesian updating after assigning the “preliminary probability” 1/4 to the statement S: “Today is Tuesday and the coin flip is heads.” (This preliminary probability obtains relative to a specific proper subset I of her available information.) Pust objects that her preliminary probability for S is really zero, because she could not be in an epistemic situation in which S is true. I reply that the impossibility of being in such an…Read more
  •  190
    Transglobal evidentialism-reliabilism
    Acta Analytica 22 (4): 281-300. 2007.
    We propose an approach to epistemic justification that incorporates elements of both reliabilism and evidentialism, while also transforming these elements in significant ways. After briefly describing and motivating the non-standard version of reliabilism that Henderson and Horgan call “transglobal” reliabilism, we harness some of Henderson and Horgan’s conceptual machinery to provide a non-reliabilist account of propositional justification (i.e., evidential support). We then invoke this account…Read more
  •  32
    Disagreement affords humans as members of epistemic communities important opportunities for refining or improving their epistemic situations with respect to many of their beliefs. To get such epistemic gains, one needs to explore and gauge one’s own epistemic situation and the epistemic situations of others. Accordingly, a fitting response to disagreement regarding some matter, p, typically will turn on the resolution of two strongly interrelated questions: (1) whether p, and (2) why one’s inter…Read more
  •  176
    Expressivism, Yes! Relativism, No!
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 1 73-98. 2006.
  •  70
    Newcomb's Problem Revisited
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 22 4-15. 2015.
  •  104
  •  47
    Editors' Introduction
    with John Tienson and Matjaž Potrč
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (S1): 7-8. 2002.
  •  115
    You are given a choice between two envelopes. You are told, reliably, that each envelope has some money in it—some whole number of dollars, say—and that one envelope contains twice as much money as the other. You don’t know which has the higher amount and which has the lower. You choose one, but are given the opportunity to switch to the other. Here is an argument that it is rationally preferable to switch: Let x be the quantity of money in your chosen envelope. Then the quantity in the other is…Read more