•  84
    Representations without Rules
    with John Tienson
    Philosophical Topics 17 (1): 147-174. 1989.
  •  83
    Practicing safe epistemology
    Philosophical Studies 102 (3). 2001.
    Reliablists have argued that the important evaluative epistemic concept of being justified in holding a belief, at least to the extent that that concept is associated with knowledge, is best understood as concerned with the objective appropriateness of the processes by which a given belief is generated and sustained. In particular, they hold that a belief is justified only when it is fostered by processes that are reliable (at least minimally so) in the believer’s actual world.[1] Of course, rel…Read more
  •  80
    The semantic blindness objection to contextualism challenges the view that there is no incompatibility between (i) denials of external-world knowledge in contexts where radical-deception scenarios are salient, and (ii) affirmations of external-world knowledge in contexts where such scenarios are not salient. Contextualism allegedly attributes a gross and implausible form of semantic incompetence in the use of the concept of knowledge to people who are otherwise quite competent in its use; this b…Read more
  •  75
    Connectionism and the commitments of folk psychology
    with John Tienson
    Philosophical Perspectives 9 127-52. 1995.
  •  74
    Henderson and Horgan set out a broad new approach to epistemology. They defend the roles of the a priori and conceptual analysis, but with an essential empirical dimension. 'Transglobal reliability' is the key to epistemic justification. The question of which cognitive processes are reliable depends on contingent facts about human capacities.
  •  74
    Core and Ancillary Epistemic Virtues
    Acta Analytica 33 (3): 295-309. 2018.
    We argue, primarily by appeal to phenomenological considerations related to the experiential aspects of agency, that belief fixation is broadly agentive; although it is rarely voluntary, nonetheless, it is phenomenologically agentive because of its significant phenomenological similarities to voluntary-agency experience. An important consequence is that epistemic rationality, as a central feature of belief fixation, is an agentive notion. This enables us to introduce and develop a distinction be…Read more
  •  73
    Materialism: Matters Of Definition, Defense, and Deconstruction
    Philosophical Studies 131 (1): 157-183. 2006.
    How should the metaphysical hypothesis of materialism be formulated? What strategies look promising for defending this hypothesis? How good are the prospects for its successful defense, especially in light of the infamous "hard problem" of phenomenal consciousness? I will say something about each of these questions
  •  72
    How to be realistic about folk psychology
    Philosophical Psychology 1 (1): 69-81. 1988.
    Folk psychological realism is the view that folk psychology is true and that people really do have propositional attitudes, whereas anti-realism is the view that folk psychology is false and people really do not have propositional attitudes. We argue that anti-realism is not worthy of acceptance and that realism is eminently worthy of acceptance. However, it is plainly epistemically possible to favor either of two forms of folk realism: scientific or non-scientific. We argue that non-scientific …Read more
  •  70
    Newcomb's Problem Revisited
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 22 4-15. 2015.
  •  68
    In recent years, defenses of moral realism have embraced what we call new wave moral semantics', which construes the semantic workings of moral terms like good' and right' as akin to the semantic workings of natural-kind terms in science and also takes inspiration from functionalist themes in the philosophy of mind. This sort of semantic view which we find in the metaethical views of David Brink, Richard Boyd, Peter Railton, is the crucial semantical underpinning of a naturalistic brand of moral…Read more
  •  68
    In “Generalized Conditionalization and the Sleeping Beauty Problem,” Anna Mahtani and I offer a new argument for thirdism that relies on what we call “generalized conditionalization.” Generalized conditionalization goes beyond conventional conditionalization in two respects: first, by sometimes deploying a space of synchronic, essentially temporal, candidate-possibilities that are not “prior” possibilities; and second, by allowing for the use of preliminary probabilities that arise by first brac…Read more
  •  64
    Supervenient bridge laws
    Philosophy of Science 45 (2): 227-249. 1978.
    I invoke the conceptual machinery of contemporary possible-world semantics to provide an account of the metaphysical status of "bridge laws" in intertheoretic reductions. I argue that although bridge laws are not definitions, and although they do not necessarily reflect attribute-identities, they are supervenient. I.e., they are true in all possible worlds in which the reducing theory is true
  •  61
    Humean Causation and Kim’s Theory of Events
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (4). 1980.
    In recent years Jaegwon Kim has propounded and elaborated an influential theory of events. He takes an event to be the exemplification of an empirical property by a concrete object at a time. He also has proposed and endorsed a version of the “Humean” tradition concerning causation: the view that causal relations between concrete events depend upon general "covering laws." But although his explication of the covering-law conception of causation seems quite natural within the framework of his the…Read more
  •  60
    The case against events
    Philosophical Review 87 (1): 28-47. 1978.
  •  55
    © Mind Association 2018Gila Sher’s Epistemic Friction is a bold and ambitious book, with many interesting things to say not only about knowledge, truth, and logic but also about matters ontological. It often requires the reader to construe it hermeneutically, but repays the effort of doing so.She coins the expression ‘epistemic friction’ to refer to constraints on a system of knowledge, coming from both the world and the mind. She says, ‘The world as the object or target of our theories restrict…Read more
  •  55
    Resisting the tyranny of terminology: The general dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science
    with John Tienson
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5): 643-643. 1998.
    What van Gelder calls the dynamical hypothesis is only a special case of what we here dub the general dynamical hypothesis. His terminology makes it easy to overlook important alternative dynamical approaches in cognitive science. Connectionist models typically conform to the general dynamical hypothesis, but not to van Gelder's.
  •  52
    Soft laws
    with John Tienson
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1): 256-279. 1990.
  •  52
    Editor's Introduction
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 7-7. 2003.
  •  51
    Review of Levine's Purple Haze (review)
    Noûs 40 (3). 2006.
  •  51
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind (edited book)
    with John L. Tienson
    Kluwer Academic Publishers. 1991.
    "A third of the papers in this volume originated at the 1987 Spindel Conference ... at Memphis State University"--Pref.