•  10
    Philosophical Perspectives on Bioethics (edited book)
    with Joseph Boyle
    University of Toronto Press. 1996.
    The contributors to the volume discuss various approaches to bioethical thinking and the political and institutional contexts of bioethics, addressing underlying concerns about the purposes of its practice.
  • Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (review)
    Philosophy in Review 5 310-313. 1985.
  • C.L. Ten, Mill On Liberty (review)
    Philosophy in Review 1 229-232. 1981.
  •  1
    Necessary Truth a Book of Readings
    with John Hayden Woods
    Random House. 1969.
  •  1
    Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 8 (4): 149-152. 1988.
  •  25
    Subjectivity and Moral Standing
    Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy 8 1-15. 1986.
  •  22
    The Carnivore Strikes Back
    Dialogue 23 (4): 661-668. 1984.
    Since philosophers began thinking seriously about the moral status of non-human animals, many of the practices we once took for granted have come to be condemned as unjustifiable, among them our reliance on animals as a food source. While the arguments which have been adduced in support of moral vegetarianism invoke quite different moral frameworks, they begin with a common concern for the welfare of animals. In the real world of practising vegetarians, this concern tends to be subordinated to c…Read more
  •  19
    Catching Up With Castañeda
    Dialogue 14 (4): 671-685. 1975.
    Remember the fifties? That was, among other things, when it was outré for moral philosophers acutally to use moral discourse and de rigueur to theorize about its use. It was when we all read Stevenson and Hare and learned to believe that moral judgments had no truth values and were used to express emotion or to issue imperatives. It was when we came to realize that all previous moral philosophy rested on the mistake of supposing that moral judgments were propositions. How remote it all seems now…Read more
  •  13
    Critical Notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (4): 623-640. 2005.
  •  46
    Toward a Credible View of Abortion
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (1). 1974.
    As little as a decade ago most moral philosophers still believed that the exercise of their craft did not include defending positions on actual moral problems. More recently they have come to their senses, one happy result being a spate of articles in the last few years on the subject of abortion. These discussions have contributed much toward an understanding of the abortion issue, but for the most part they have not attempted a full analysis of the morality of abortion. Such an analysis is too…Read more
  •  92
    Positive Sexism
    Social Philosophy and Policy 5 (1): 204. 1987.
    No one who cares about equal opportunity can derive much comfort from the present occupational distribution of working women. In the various industrial societies of the West, women comprise between one quarter and one-half of the national labor force. However, they tend to clustered in employment sectors – especially clerical, sales, and service J occupations – which rank relatively low in remuneration, status, autonomy, and other perquisites. Meanwhile, the more prestigious and rewarding manage…Read more
  •  90
    A matter of life and death
    Noûs 10 (2): 145-171. 1976.
  •  39
    More light on the later mill
    Philosophical Review 83 (4): 504-527. 1974.
  •  54
    Hare's arguments against ethical naturalism
    Journal of Philosophy 64 (23): 779-791. 1967.
  •  14
    Consequences of Utilitarianism
    Dialogue 7 (4): 639-642. 1969.
    This is a book built round an argument. Several variants of the argument are offered, and I shall consider but one of them. It is directed against the following act utilitarian principle:AU: An act is right if and only if it would have best consequences The argument may be freely rendered as follows. Suppose that we have an agent, Smith, in a society, S, such that the following conditions are satisfied:C1: Smith accepts AU and attempts always to act in accordance with itC2: Smith is rational: he…Read more
  •  928
    The moral foundation of rights
    Oxford University Press. 1987.
    What does it mean for someone to have a moral right to something? What kinds of creatures can have rights, and which rights can they have? While rights are indispensable to our moral and political thinking, they are also mysterious and controversial; as long as these controversies remain unsolved, rights will remain vulnerable to skepticism. Here, Sumner constructs both a coherent concept of a moral right and a workable substantive theory of rights to provide the moral foundation necessary to di…Read more
  •  12
    Reply to Hurka and Copp
    Dialogue 28 (1): 149-. 1989.
    I am deeply indebted to Tom Hurka and David Copp for the careful attention they have given to some of the central motifs in The Moral Foundation of Rights. By doing their job so well they have simplified mine considerably. Their exposition of my views is a model of fairness and accuracy; I need therefore waste no time disclaiming attributions or complaining about misrepresentation. Furthermore, they have shown admirable resolve in choosing to ignore the book's relatively peripheral concerns, eve…Read more
  •  1
    Book Review (review)
    Law and Philosophy 32 (2-3): 377-383. 2013.
  •  13
    Perfectionism
    Philosophical Review 104 (1): 151. 1995.
  •  166
    Welfare, Happiness, and Pleasure
    Utilitas 4 (2): 199-223. 1992.
    Time and philosophical fashion have not been kind to hedonism. After flourishing for three centuries or so in its native empiricist habitat, it has latterly all but disappeared from the scene. Does it now merit even passing attention, for other than nostalgic purposes? Like endangered species, discredited ideas do sometimes manage to make a comeback. Is hedonism due for a revival of this sort? Perhaps it is overly optimistic to think that it could ever flourish again in its original form; the ev…Read more
  •  88
    Is Virtue Its Own Reward?: L. W. SUMNER
    Social Philosophy and Policy 15 (1): 18-36. 1998.
    If I lead a life of virtue, that may well be good for you. But will it also be good for me? The idea that it will—or even must—is an ancient one, and its appeal runs deep. For if this idea is correct then we can provide everyone with a good reason—arguably the best reason—for being virtuous. However, for all the effort which has been invested in defending the idea, by some of the best minds in the history of philosophy, it remains unproven. Worse, in this skeptical age hardly anyone really belie…Read more
  •  9
    Deliberating on Death
    Dialogue 23 (3): 503-508. 1984.
    As a distinct academic subdiscipline medical ethics is only about fifteen years old, but during that brief lifespan it has managed to generate a literature so vast that only specialists and speedreaders can now hope to keep up with more than a small fraction of it. When a literature has achieved this density new contributions must bear the burden of showing that they advance the existing state of the art. Eike-Henner W. Kluge's book joins a well-established continuing debate on the morality of e…Read more