•  5
    Controversy has recently erupted, at least in a recent story in the Independent, over the question of whether Brown's Philosophy Department has been inappropriately exclusionary of courses in other departments, of diverse philosophical traditions, and of non-white philosophers. These are questions well worth asking, although the article's critical stance requires some scrutiny. It is worth supplementing the article with some information that might help students think about whether they ought to …Read more
  •  112
    Reply to Wiens
    European Journal of Political Theory 15 (3): 353-362. 2016.
    In Human Nature and the Limits of Political Philosophy, I argued that justice might require things of people that they cannot bring themselves to do. A central step was to argue that this does not entail an inability to ‘do’ the putatively required thing. David Wiens challenges that argument of mine, and this piece is my reply.
  •  44
    :Cambridge Companion to Rawls
    Ethics 114 (3): 608-615. 2004.
    John Rawls is the most significant and influential philosopher and moral philosopher of the twentieth century. His work has profoundly shaped contemporary discussions of social, political and economic justice in philosophy, law, political science, economics and other social disciplines. In this exciting collection of new essays, many of the world's leading political and moral theorists discuss the full range of Rawls's contribution to the concepts of political and economic justice, democracy, li…Read more
  •  433
    Liberal associationism and the rights of states
    Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1-2): 425-449. 2013.
    It is often argued that if one holds a liberal political philosophy about individual rights against the state and the community, then one cannot consistently say that a state that violates those principles is owed the right of noninterference. How could the rights of the collective trump the rights of individuals in a liberal view? I believe that this debate calls for more reflection, on the relation between liberalism and individualism. I will sketch a conception of liberalism in which there is…Read more
  •  4333
    Utopophobia
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (2): 113-134. 2014.
  •  717
  •  26
    Democracy (edited book)
    Blackwell. 2001.
    Democracy brings together some of the most sophisticated thinking on democratic theory in one concise volume. Written by experts in the field, these contemporary readings are distinctively philosophical, but will appeal to students in historical, empirical, legal, or policy- oriented disciplines which deal with democratic theory.
  •  1184
    Political Quality
    Social Philosophy and Policy 17 (1): 127. 2000.
    Political equality is in tension with political quality, and quality has recently been neglected. My thesis is that proper attention to the quality of democratic procedures and their outcomes requires that we accept substantive inequalities of political input in the interest of increasing input overall. Mainly, I hope to refute political egalitarianism, the view that justice or legitimacy requires substantive political equality, specifically equal availability of power or influence over collecti…Read more
  •  269
    Methodological moralism in political philosophy
    Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20 (3): 385-402. 2017.
  •  429
    The place of self-interest and the role of power in deliberative democracy
    with Jane Mansbridge, James Bohman, Simone Chambers, Andreas Føllesdal, Archon Fung, Cristina Lafont, Bernard Manin, and José Luis Martí
    Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (1): 64-100. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  4
    Book Reviews (review)
    Ethics 113 (4): 911-914. 2003.
  •  290
    On Sunstein's Infotopia
    Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 56 (119): 14-29. 2009.
    Sunstein argues that democratic theory has recently rested its normative claims on a vast but empirically uninformed optimism about the ability of collective deliberation to lead to morally and rationally better decisions. Once that question is considered empirically, he argues, deliberation turns out to be mixed at best, and a disaster at worst. I want to suggest that Sunstein exaggerates the claims of the deliberative democrats, and interprets the empirical literature against deliberation in a…Read more
  •  23
    Legislative Intent and Other Essays on Law, Politics and Morality
    Philosophical Review 104 (4): 605. 1995.
    Gerald MacCallum taught philosophy at the University of Wisconsin from 1961 until 1977. The stroke he suffered in that year prevented him from further teaching. He continued to write, even through the crippling effects of a second stroke, until his death in 1987. His final project was the Prentice Hall Foundations in Philosophy book, Political Philosophy. The present collection brings together papers, published and unpublished, spanning his writing career. I hope in this short space to convey so…Read more
  •  140
    Suppose justice depends on some very unlikely good behavior. In that case the true (or correct, or best) theory of justice might have no practical value. But then, what good would it be? I consider analogies with science and mathematics in order to test various ways of tying their the value of intellectual work to practice, though I argue that these fail. If their value, or that of some political theory, is not practical then what is good about them? As for political theory, I consider the quest…Read more
  •  273
    Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework
    Princeton University Press. 2008.
    Democracy is not naturally plausible. Why turn such important matters over to masses of people who have no expertise? Many theories of democracy answer by appealing to the intrinsic value of democratic procedure, leaving aside whether it makes good decisions. In Democratic Authority, David Estlund offers a groundbreaking alternative based on the idea that democratic authority and legitimacy must depend partly on democracy's tendency to make good decisions.Just as with verdicts in jury trials, Es…Read more
  •  6
    Reply to Copp, Gaus, Richardson, and Edmundson
    Ethics 121 (2): 354-389. 2011.
    This piece is a response to four essays that critically discuss my book Democratic Authority. In addition to responding to their specific criticisms, it takes up several methodological issues that put some of the critiques in a broader context. Among the issues discussed are “normative consent,” which I offer as a new theory of authority; the “general acceptability requirement,” which advances a broadly Rawlsian approach to political justification; and methodological questions about theory build…Read more
  •  7
    No Title available: Reviews
    Economics and Philosophy 12 (1): 113-119. 1996.
  •  611
    Justificatory Liberalism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (3): 821-825. 1999.
  •  925
    Debate: On Christiano's the constitution of equality
    Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (2): 241-252. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  678
    The Democracy/Contractualism Analogy
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (4): 387-412. 2003.