•  116
  •  386
    Review of Alva Noe, Action in Perception (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 102 (5): 259-272. 2005.
    This is a charming and engaging book that combines careful attention to the phenomenology of experience with an appreciation of the psychology and neuroscience of perception. In some of its aimsfor example, to show problems with a rigid version of a view of visual perception as an inverse optics process of constructing a static 3-D representation from static 2-D information on the retina--it succeeds admirably. As No points out, vision is a process that depends on interactions between the percei…Read more
  •  4059
    Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access
    Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15 (12): 567-575. 2011.
    One of the most important issues concerning the foundations ofconscious perception centerson thequestion of whether perceptual consciousness is rich or sparse. The overflow argument uses a form of ‘iconic memory’ toarguethatperceptual consciousnessisricher (i.e.,has a higher capacity) than cognitive access: when observing a complex scene we are conscious of more than we can report or think about. Recently, the overflow argumenthas been challenged both empirically and conceptually. This paper rev…Read more
  •  307
    This volume of Ned Block's writings collects his papers on consciousness, functionalism, and representationism. A number of these papers treat the significance of the multiple realizability of mental states for the mind-body problem -- a theme that has concerned Block since the 1960s. One paper on this topic considers the upshot for the mind-body problem of the possibility of a robot that is functionally like us but physically different -- as is Commander Data of _Star Trek's_ second generation.…Read more
  •  1
    The Mind as Software in the Brain
    In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology, Oxford University Press. 2003.
  •  91
    Biology versus computation in the study of consciousness
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1): 159-165. 1997.
    The distinction between phenomenal (P) and access (A) consciousness arises from the battle between biological and computational approaches to the mind. If P = A, the computationalists are right; but if not, the biological nature of P yields its scientific nature.
  •  128
    Overflow, access, and attention
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 530-548. 2007.
    In this response to 32 commentators, I start by clarifying the overflow argument. I explain why the distinction between generic and specific phenomenology is important and why we are justified in acknowledging specific phenomenology in the overflow experiments. Other issues discussed are the relations among report, cognitive access, and attention; panpsychic disaster; the mesh between psychology and neuroscience; and whether consciousness exists.
  •  604
    The Defective Armchair: A Reply to Tye
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 3 (2): 159-165. 2014.
    Michael Tye's response to my “Grain” (Block ) and “Windows” (Block ) raises general metaphilosophical issues about the value of intuitions and judgments about one's perceptions and the relations of those intuitions and judgments to empirical research, as well as specific philosophical issues about the relation between seeing, attention and de re thought. I will argue that Tye's appeal to what is (§. 2) “intuitively obvious, once we reflect upon these cases” (“intuition”) is problematic. I will a…Read more
  •  79
    Imagery (edited book)
    MIT Press. 1981.
    The "great debate" in cognitive science today is about the nature of mental images. One side says images are basically pictures in the head. The other side says they are like the symbol structures in computers. If the picture-in-the-head theorists are right, then computers will never be able to think like people.This book contains the most intelligible and incisive articles in the debate, articles by cognitive psychologists, computer scientists and philosophers. The most exciting imagery phenome…Read more
  •  12
    Straw materialism
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (3): 347-348. 1978.
  •  24
    Area MT/V5 in a bottle?
    Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (2): 46-52. 2005.
  •  397
    What Is Dennett’s Theory a Theory of?
    Philosophical Topics 22 (1/2): 23-40. 1994.
    A convenient locus of discussion is provided by Dennett.
  •  30
    Functional Role and Truth Conditions
    with John Campell
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 61 (1): 157-184. 1987.
  •  100
    Argues for a failure of correspondence between perceptual representation and what it is like to perceive. If what it is like to perceive is grounded in perceptual representation, then, using considerations of veridical representation, we can show that inattentive peripheral perception is less representationally precise than attentive foveal perception. However, there is empirical evidence to the contrary. The conclusion is that perceptual representation cannot ground what it is like to perceive
  •  75
    Readings In Philosophy Of Psychology, V (edited book)
    Harvard University Press. 1981.
    Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and ... V. Influence of imaged pictures and sounds on detection of visual and auditory signals. ...
  •  279
    Mental Pictures and Cognitive Science
    Philosophical Review 92 (4): 499--542. 1983.
    Such claims are part 0f a viewpoint according t0 which mental images represent in thc manner of pictures. It is very natural t0 think that such claims are confused or nonsensical. One of my purposes here is a limited dcfcnsc of this supposedly confused doctrine, especially against its chief cognitive science rival. But this..
  •  1942
    Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap
    Philosophical Review 108 (1): 1-46. 1999.
    The explanatory gap . Consciousness is a mystery. No one has ever given an account, even a highly speculative, hypothetical, and incomplete account of how a physical thing could have phenomenal states. Suppose that consciousness is identical to a property of the brain, say activity in the pyramidal cells of layer 5 of the cortex involving reverberatory circuits from cortical layer 6 to the thalamus and back to layers 4 and 6,as Crick and Koch have suggested for visual consciousness. .) Still, th…Read more
  •  213
    Paradox and cross purposes in recent work on consciousness
    Cognition 79 (1-2): 197--219. 2001.
    Dehaene and Naccache, Dennett and Jack and Shallice “see convergence coming from many different quarters on a version of the neuronal global workspace model†(Dennett, p. 1). (Boldface references are to papers in this volume.) On the contrary, even within this volume, there are commitments to very different perspectives on consciousness. And these differing perspectives are based on tacit differences in philosophical starting places that should be made explicit.  Indeed, it is not clear …Read more
  •  126
    The Harder Problem of Consciousness
    Journal of Philosophy 99 (8): 391. 2002.
  •  1231
    Mental (or semantic) holism is the doctrine that the identity of a belief content (or the meaning of a sentence that expresses it) is determined by its place in the web of beliefs or sentences comprising a whole theory or group of theories. It can be contrasted with two other views: atomism and molecularism. Molecularism characterizes meaning and content in terms of relatively small parts of the web in a way that allows many different theories to share those parts. For example, the meaning of 'c…Read more
  •  1306
    The Anna Karenina Theory of the Unconscious
    Neuropsychoanalysis 13 (1): 34-37. 2011.
    The Anna Karenina Theory says: all conscious states are alike; each unconscious state is unconscious in its own way. This note argues that many components have to function properly to produce consciousness, but failure in any one of many different ones can yield an unconscious state in different ways. In that sense the Anna Karenina theory is true. But in another respect it is false: kinds of unconsciousness depend on kinds of consciousness
  •  256
    Behaviorism revisited
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (5): 977-978. 2001.
    O'Regan and Noe declare that the qualitative character of experience is constituted by the nature of the sensorimotor contingencies at play when we perceive. Sensorimotor contingencies are a highly restricted set of input-output relations. The restriction excludes contingencies that don’t essentially involve perceptual systems. Of course if the ‘sensory’ in ‘sensorimotor’ were to be understood mentalistically, the thesis would not be of much interest, so I assume that these contingencies are to …Read more
  •  106
    Partial awareness and the illusion of phenomenal consciousness
    with Sid Kouider, Vincent de Gardelle, and Emmanuel Dupoux
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5): 510-510. 2007.
    The dissociation Block provides between phenomenal and access consciousness (P-consciousness and A-consciousness) captures much of our intuition about conscious experience. However, it raises a major methodological puzzle, and is not uniquely supported by the empirical evidence. We provide an alternative interpretation based on the notion of levels of representation and partial awareness
  •  120
    How many concepts of consciousness?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 272-287. 1995.
    With some help from the commentators, a few adjustments to the characterizations of A-consciousness and P-consciousness can avoid some trivial cases of one without the other. But it still seems that the case for the existence of P without A is stronger than that for A without P. If indeed there can be P without A, but not A without P, this would be a remarkable result that would need explanation.
  •  1076
    Consciousness is a mongrel concept: there are a number of very different "consciousnesses". Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that state
  •  539
    Are absent qualia impossible?
    Philosophical Review 89 (2): 257-74. 1980.