•  41
    Comparative cognitive studies, not folk phylogeny, please
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1): 122-123. 1996.
    Barresi & Moore (B&M) provide a useful tool for the comparative study of social cognition that could, however, be improved by more subtle analysis of first person information about intentional relations. Knowledge of misrepresentation also needs to be better handled within the theory. I urge skepticism about B&M's sweeping phylogenetic claims.
  •  66
    Cognitive ethology: Slayers, skeptics, and proponents
    with Marc Bekoff
    In R. Mitchell, Nicholas S. Thompson & H. L. Miles (eds.), Anthropomorphism, Anecdotes, and Animals, Suny Press. pp. 313--334. 1997.
  •  197
    Animal play and the evolution of morality: An ethological approach
    with Marc Bekoff
    Topoi 24 (2): 125-135. 2005.
      In this paper we argue that there is much to learn about “wild justice” and the evolutionary origins of morality – behaving fairly – by studying social play behavior in group-living mammals. Because of its relatively wide distribution among the mammals, ethological investigation of play, informed by interdisciplinary cooperation, can provide a comparative perspective on the evolution of ethical behavior that is broader than is provided by the usual focus on primate sociality. Careful analysis …Read more
  •  167
    The discovery of animal consciousness: An optimistic assessment (review)
    Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 10 (3): 217-225. 1997.
  •  407
    Animal consciousness
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2005.
  •  40
    Philosophy of Biology (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 14 (4): 423-427. 1991.
  •  46
    Does evidence from ethology support bicoded cognitive maps?
    with Shane Zappettini
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (5): 570-571. 2013.
    The presumption that navigation requires a cognitive map leads to its conception as an abstract computational problem. Instead of loading the question in favor of an inquiry into the metric structure and evolutionary origin of cognitive maps, the task should first be to establish that a map-like representation actually is operative in real animals navigating real environments
  •  162
    Mental content
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (4): 537-553. 1992.
    Daniel Dennett and Stephen Stich have independently, but similarly, argued that the contents of mental states cannot be specified precisely enough for the purposes of scientific prediction and explanation. Dennett takes this to support his view that the proper role for mentalistic terms in science is heuristic. Stich takes it to support his view that cognitive science should be done without reference to mental content at all. I defend a realist understanding of mental content against these attac…Read more
  •  99
    Erratum to: Synthese special issue: representing philosophy
    with Tony Beavers
    Synthese 183 (2): 277-277. 2011.
  •  806
    Animal pain
    Noûs 38 (4): 617-643. 2004.
    Which nonhuman animals experience conscious pain?1 This question is central to the debate about animal welfare, as well as being of basic interest to scientists and philosophers of mind. Nociception—the capacity to sense noxious stimuli—is one of the most primitive sensory capacities. Neurons functionally specialized for nociception have been described in invertebrates such as the leech Hirudo medicinalis and the marine snail Aplysia californica (Walters 1996). Is all nociception accompanied by …Read more
  •  145
    Biological function, adaptation, and natural design
    with Marc Bekoff
    Philosophy of Science 62 (4): 609-622. 1995.
    Recently something close to a consensus about the best way to naturalize the notion of biological function appears to be emerging. Nonetheless, teleological notions in biology remain controversial. In this paper we provide a naturalistic analysis for the notion of natural design. Many authors assume that natural design should be assimilated directly to function. Others find the notion problematic because it suggests that evolution is a directed process. We argue that both of these views are mist…Read more
  •  185
    Teleological Notions in Biology
    In Peter Adamson (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2012.
    Teleological terms such as "function" and "design" appear frequently in the biological sciences. Examples of teleological claims include: A (biological) function of stotting by antelopes is to communicate to predators that they have been detected. Eagles' wings are (naturally) designed for soaring. Teleological notions were commonly associated with the pre-Darwinian view that the biological realm provides evidence of conscious design by a supernatural creator. Even after creationist viewpoints w…Read more
  •  219
      Many psychologists and philosophers believe that the close correlation between human language and human concepts makes the attribution of concepts to nonhuman animals highly questionable. I argue for a three-part approach to attributing concepts to animals. The approach goes beyond the usual discrimination tests by seeking evidence for self-monitoring of discrimination errors. Such evidence can be collected without relying on language and, I argue, the capacity for error-detection can only be …Read more
  •  157
    Species of Mind: The Philosophy and Biology of Cognitive Ethology (edited book)
    with Marc Bekoff
    MIT Press. 1997.
    The heart of this book is the reciprocal relationship between philosophical theories of mind and empirical studies of animal cognition.
  •  808
    Primatologists generally agree that monkeys lack higher-order intentional capacities related to theory of mind. Yet the discovery of the so-called "mirror neurons" in monkeys suggests to many neuroscientists that they have the rudiments of intentional understanding. Given a standard philosophical view about intentional understanding, which requires higher-order intentionahty, a paradox arises. Different ways of resolving the paradox are assessed, using evidence from neural, cognitive, and behavi…Read more
  •  113
    Intentionality, social play, and definition
    with Marc Bekoff
    Biology and Philosophy 9 (1): 63-74. 1994.
    Social play is naturally characterized in intentional terms. An evolutionary account of social play could help scientists to understand the evolution of cognition and intentionality. Alexander Rosenberg (1990) has argued that if play is characterized intentionally or functionally, it is not a behavioral phenotype suitable for evolutionary explanation. If he is right, his arguments would threaten many projects in cognitive ethology. We argue that Rosenberg's arguments are unsound and that intenti…Read more
  •  62
    How to reason without words: inference as categorization
    with Professor Ronaldo Vigo
    Cognitive Processing 10 77-88. 2009.
    The idea that reasoning is a singular accomplishment of the human species has an ancient pedigree.Yet this idea remains as controversial as it is ancient. Those who would deny reasoning to nonhuman animals typically hold a language-based conception of inference which places it beyond the reach of languageless creatures. Others reject such an anthropocentric conception of reasoning on the basis of similar performance by humans and animals in some reasoning tasks, such as transitive inference. Her…Read more
  •  164
    Cognitive ethology and the intentionality of animal behavior
    with Marc Bekoff
    Mind and Language 10 (4): 313-328. 1995.
    Cognitive ethologists are in need of a good theoretical framework for attributing intentional states. Heyes and Dickinson (1990) present criteria that they claim are necessary for an intentional explanation of behavior to be justified. They suggest that questions of intentionality can only be investigated under controlled laboratory conditions and they apply their criteria to laboratory experiments to argue that the common behavior of approaching food is not intentional in most animals. We dispu…Read more
  •  51
    Social play is more than a Pavlovian romp
    with Marc Bekoff
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (2): 250-251. 2000.
    Some aspects of play may be explained by Pavlovian learning processes, but others are not so easily handled. Especially when there is a chance that specific actions can be misinterpreted; animals alter their behavior to reduce the likelihood that this will occur. The flexibility and fine-tuning of play make it an ideal candidate for comparative and evolutionary cognitive studies.
  •  365
    A skeptic's progress
    Biology and Philosophy 17 (5): 695-702. 2002.
    Seven chimpanzees in twenty-seven experiments run over the course of five years at his University of Louisiana laboratory in New Iberia, Louisiana, are at the heart of Daniel Povinelli’s case that chimpanzee thinking about the physical world is not at all like that of humans. Chimps, according to Povinelli and his coauthors James Reaux, Laura Theall, and Steve Giambrone, are phenomenally quick at learning to associate visible features of tools with specific uses of those tools, but they appear to …Read more
  •  63
    The evolution of rational demons
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (5): 742-742. 2000.
    If fast and frugal heuristics are as good as they seem to be, who needs logic and probability theory? Fast and frugal heuristics depend for their success on reliable structure in the environment. In passive environments, there is relatively little change in structure as a consequence of individual choices. But in social interactions with competing agents, the environment may be structured by agents capable of exploiting logical and probabilistic weaknesses in competitors' heuristics. Aspirations…Read more
  •  4
    Animal consciousness
    with Mark Bekoff
    In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, Blackwell. 2007.
  •  535
    Prolegomena to any future artificial moral agent
    Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 12 (3): 251--261. 2000.
    As arti® cial intelligence moves ever closer to the goal of producing fully autonomous agents, the question of how to design and implement an arti® cial moral agent (AMA) becomes increasingly pressing. Robots possessing autonomous capacities to do things that are useful to humans will also have the capacity to do things that are harmful to humans and other sentient beings. Theoretical challenges to developing arti® cial moral agents result both from controversies among ethicists about moral theo…Read more
  •  202
    Mental content and evolutionary explanation
    Biology and Philosophy 7 (1): 1-12. 1992.
    Cognitive ethology is the comparative study of animal cognition from an evolutionary perspective. As a sub-discipline of biology it shares interest in questions concerning the immediate causes and development of behavior. As a part of ethology it is also concerned with questions about the function and evolution of behavior. I examine some recent work in cognitive ethology, and I argue that the notions of mental content and representation are important to enable researchers to answer questions an…Read more
  •  192
    Fish Cognition and Consciousness
    Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 26 (1): 25-39. 2013.
    Questions about fish consciousness and cognition are receiving increasing attention. In this paper, I explain why one must be careful to avoid drawing conclusions too hastily about this hugely diverse set of species
  •  95
    It is a truism among ethologists that one must not forget that animals perceive and represent the world differently from humans. Sometimes this caution is phrased in terms of von Uexküll’s Umwelt concept. Yet it seems possible (perhaps even unavoidable) to adopt a common ontological framework when comparing different species of mind. For some purposes it seems sufficient to ­anchor comparative cognition in common-sense categories; bats echolocate insects (or a subset of them) after all. But for …Read more
  •  71
    Conditioned anti-anthropomorphism
    Comparative Cognition and Behavior Reviews 2 147-150. 2007.
    How should scientists react to anthropomorphism (defined for the purposes of this paper as the attribution of mental states or properties to nonhuman animals)? Many thoughtful scientists have attempted to accommodate some measure of anthropomorphism in their approaches to animal behavior. But Wynne will have none of it. We reject his argument against anthropomorphism and argue that he does not pay sufficient attention to the historical facts or to the details of alternative approaches.
  •  178
    The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy: A developed dynamic reference work
    with Uri Nodelman and Edward N. Zalta
    In James Moor & Terrell Ward Bynum (eds.), Metaphilosophy, Blackwell. pp. 210-228. 2002.
    In this entry, the authors outline the goals of a "dynamic reference work", and explain how the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy has been designed to achieve those goals.
  •  201
    Animal Minds, Cognitive Ethology, and Ethics
    with Marc Bekoff
    The Journal of Ethics 11 (3): 299-317. 2007.
    Our goal in this paper is to provide enough of an account of the origins of cognitive ethology and the controversy surrounding it to help ethicists to gauge for themselves how to balance skepticism and credulity about animal minds when communicating with scientists. We believe that ethicists’ arguments would benefit from better understanding of the historical roots of ongoing controversies. It is not appropriate to treat some widely reported results in animal cognition as if their interpretation…Read more
  •  122
    Synthese special issue: representing philosophy
    with Tony Beavers
    Synthese 182 (2): 181-183. 2011.
    This special issue of Synthese discusses conceptual, ontological, technological, ethical, political, and professional dimensions of attempts to represent the entire discipline of philosophy. One of our goals with this issue was to collect in one place several of the leading projects in digital philosophy so that the profession can begin to discern and debate what might be the best practices for the representation of philosophy in the 21st century.