•  48
    It is difficult to imagine mathematics without its symbolic language. It is especially difficult to imagine doing mathematics without using mathematical notation. Nevertheless, that is how mathematics was done for most of human history. It was only at the end of the sixteenth century that mathematicians began to develop systems of mathematical symbols . It is startling to consider how rapidly mathematical notation evolved. Viète is usually taken to have initiated this development with his Isagog…Read more
  •  78
    Lakatos as historian of mathematics
    Philosophia Mathematica 5 (1): 42-64. 1997.
    This paper discusses the connection between the actual history of mathematics and Lakatos's philosophy of mathematics, in three parts. The first points to studies by Lakatos and others which support his conception of mathematics and its history. In the second I suggest that the apparent poverty of Lakatosian examples may be due to the way in which the history of mathematics is usually written. The third part argues that Lakatos is right to hold philosophy accountable to history, even if Lakatos'…Read more
  • Proceedings of the Symposium on Mathematical Practice and Cognition Ii: A Symposium at the Aisb/Iacap World Congress 2012 (edited book)
    Society for the Study of Artificial Intelligence and the Simulation of Behaviour. 2012.
  • The Philosophy of Mathematics of Imre Lakatos
    Dissertation, Oxford University. 1995.
    DPhil dissertation, University of Oxford.
  •  55
    Re-reading soviet philosophy: Bakhurst on ilyenkov
    Studies in East European Thought 44 (1): 1-31. 1992.
  •  29
    History, methodology and early algebra 1
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8 (2): 113-124. 1994.
    The limits of ‘criterial rationality’ (that is, rationality as rule‐following) have been extensively explored in the philosophy of science by Kuhn and others. In this paper I attempt to extend this line of enquiry into mathematics by means of a pair of case studies in early algebra. The first case is the Ars Magna (Nuremburg 1545) by Jerome Cardan (1501–1576), in which a then recently‐discovered formula for finding the roots of some cubic equations is extended to cover all cubics and proved. The…Read more
  •  25
    Albert Lautman, ou la dialectique dans les mathématiques
    Philosophiques 37 (1): 75-94. 2010.
    Dans cet article, j’explore dans un premier temps la conception que se fait Lautman de la dialectique en examinant ses références à Platon et Heidegger. Je compare ensuite les structures dialectiques identifiées par Lautman dans les mathématiques contemporaines avec celles qui émergent de ses sources philosophiques. Enfin, je soutiens que les structures qu’il a découvertes dans les mathématiques sont plus riches que le suggère son modèle platonicien, et que la distinction « ontologique » de Heid…Read more
  •  426
    Williams on Dawkins – response
    Think 9 (26): 21-27. 2010.
    Peter Williams complains that Richard Dawkins wraps his naturalism in ‘a fake finery of counterfeit meaning and purpose’. For his part, Williams has wrapped his complaint in an unoriginal and inapt analogy. The weavers in Hans Christian Andersen's fable announce that the Emperor's clothes are invisible to stupid people; almost the whole population pretends to see them for fear of being thought stupid . Fear of being thought stupid does not seem to trouble Richard Dawkins. Moreover, Williams offe…Read more
  •  66
    Three is a magic number
    The Philosophers' Magazine 44 (44): 83-88. 2009.
    Logical theory – and philosophical theory generally – is just that, theory. Generations of logic students felt a sort of unease about it without knowing what to do about it. Nowadays, students of mathematical logic feel a similar unease when faced with the fact that in standard predicate calculus, “All unicorns are sneaky” is true precisely because there are no unicorns. Blanché’s analysis reminds us that such feelings of unease may indicate a shortcoming in the theory rather than in the student…Read more
  •  210
    Proof in C17 Algebra
    Philosophia Scientiae 43-59. 2005.
    By the middle of the seventeenth century we that find that algebra is able to offer proofs in its own right. That is, by that time algebraic argument had achieved the status of proof. How did this transformation come about?
  •  58
    Lakatos: An Introduction
    Routledge. 1998.
    _Lakatos: An Introduction_ provides a thorough overview of both Lakatos's thought and his place in twentieth century philosophy. It is an essential and insightful read for students and anyone interested in the philosophy of science.
  •  69
    Books of essays
    Philosophia Mathematica 10 (1): 93-96. 2002.
  •  300
    Tu quoque, Archbishop
    Think 3 (7): 101-108. 2004.
    Brendan Larvor finds that the Archbishop of Canterbury's recent arguments about religious education are a curate's egg.
  •  40
    Reply to James Blachowicz
    The Owl of Minerva 31 (1): 53-54. 1999.
  •  1
    Michael D. Resnik, Mathematics as a Science of Patterns
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 12 (3): 287-289. 1998.
  •  142
    How to think about informal proofs
    Synthese 187 (2): 715-730. 2012.
    It is argued in this study that (i) progress in the philosophy of mathematical practice requires a general positive account of informal proof; (ii) the best candidate is to think of informal proofs as arguments that depend on their matter as well as their logical form; (iii) articulating the dependency of informal inferences on their content requires a redefinition of logic as the general study of inferential actions; (iv) it is a decisive advantage of this conception of logic that it accommodat…Read more
  •  22
    The owl and the pussycat
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (175): 233-239. 1994.
  •  89
  •  90
    This article canvasses five senses in which one might introduce an historical element into the philosophy of mathematics: 1. The temporal dimension of logic; 2. Explanatory Appeal to Context rather than to General Principles; 3. Heraclitean Flux; 4. All history is the History of Thought; and 5. History is Non-Judgmental. It concludes by adapting Bernard Williams’ distinction between ‘history of philosophy’ and ‘history of ideas’ to argue that the philosophy of mathematics is unavoidably historic…Read more
  •  339
    Two Cultures
    Cogito 12 (1): 13-16. 1998.
    The schism between analytic and continental philosophy resists repair because it is not confined to philosophers. It is a local manifestation of a far more profound and pervasive division. In 1959 C.P. Snow lamented the partition of intellectual life in to `two cultures': that of the scientist and that of the literary intellectual. If we follow the practice of most universities and bundle historical and literary studies together in the faculty of humanities on the one hand, and count pure mathem…Read more
  •  129
    Moral particularism and scientific practice
    Metaphilosophy 39 (4-5): 492-507. 2008.
    Abstract: Particularism is usually understood as a position in moral philosophy. In fact, it is a view about all reasons, not only moral reasons. Here, I show that particularism is a familiar and controversial position in the philosophy of science and mathematics. I then argue for particularism with respect to scientific and mathematical reasoning. This has a bearing on moral particularism, because if particularism about moral reasons is true, then particularism must be true with respect to reas…Read more