•  42
    Should We Be Utopophobes About Democracy in Particular?
    Political Studies Review 10 (1): 36-47. 2012.
    In his book Democratic Authority, David Estlund puts forward a case for democracy, which he labels epistemic proceduralism, that relies on democracy's ability to produce good – that is, substantively just – results. Alongside this case for democracy Estlund attacks what he labels ‘utopophobia’, an aversion to idealistic political theory. In this article I make two points. The first is a general point about what the correct level of ‘idealisation’ is in political theory. Various debates are emerg…Read more
  •  87
    Retributivists! The Harm Principle Is Not for You!
    Ethics 124 (2): 272-298. 2014.
    Retributivism is often explicitly or implicitly assumed to be compatible with the harm principle, since the harm principle (in some guises) concerns the content of the criminal law, while retributivism concerns the punishment of those that break the law. In this essay I show that retributivism should not be endorsed alongside any version of the harm principle. In fact, retributivists should reject all attempts to see the criminal law only through (other) person-affecting concepts or “grievance” …Read more
  •  9
    And Nozick begat Reagan?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 33 38-41. 2006.
  •  54
    Time and Retribution
    Law and Philosophy 33 (5): 655-682. 2014.
    Retributivists believe that punishment can be deserved, and that deserved punishment is intrinsically good or important. They also believe that certain crimes deserve certain quantities of punishment. On the plausible assumption that the overall amount of any given punishment is a function of its severity and duration, we might think that retributivists would be indifferent as to whether a punishment were long and light or short and sharp, provided the offender gets the overall amount of punishm…Read more
  •  90