•  77
    “When a speaker says something of the form A and B, he may take it for granted that A (or at least that his audience recognizes that he accepts that A) after he has said it. The proposition that A will be added to the background of common assumptions before the speaker asserts that B. Now suppose that B expresses a proposition that would, for some reason, be inappropriate to assert except in a context where A, or something entailed by A, is presupposed. Even if A is not presupposed initially, on…Read more
  •  77
    Introduction: Epistemic Modals
    Topoi 36 (1): 127-130. 2017.
    Theorists with otherwise radically different commitments agree that epistemic modals mark the necessity or possibility of a prejacent proposition relative to a body of evidence or knowledge. However, there is vast disagreement about the semantics of epistemic modals, which stems in part from the fact that statements of epistemic possibility or necessity make no explicit reference to a speaker or group, an audience, or an evidence set. This volume introduces new philosophical papers that mark a s…Read more
  •  76
    Brogaard, Berit_Replies
  •  75
  •  73
    The Philosophy and Psychology of Ambivalence: Being of Two Minds (edited book)
    with Dimitria Electra Gatzia
    Routledge. 2021.
    This volume provides novel approaches to a variety of questions about ambivalence and the role it plays in our lives. As the contributions illustrate, ambivalence finds its way into a gamut of philosophical and psychological debates about rationality, skepticism, emotions, intentionality, racism, global justice, well-being, mindfulness, and intersubjectivity. These debates concern questions like: “Is ambivalence distinct from uncertainty?”, “Does ambivalence affect the way we respond to paradoxe…Read more
  •  66
    In The Principles of Psychology, William James (1981) has long ago suggested that attending to a stimulus can make it appear more ‘vivid and clear.’ Pre-cueing, the procedure in which a cue stimulus is presented to direct a subject’s attention to the location of a test stimulus, has been used to test James’ hypothesis (Posner, 1978; Carrasco et al., 2004; Carrasco, Loula, & Ho, 2006; Yeshurun & Rashal, 2010; Carrasco, 2011). One recent debate concerns whether the effects of pre-cueing and other …Read more
  •  64
    Does Perception Have Content? (edited book)
    Oup Usa. 2014.
    This volume of new essays brings together philosophers representing many different perspectives to address central questions in the philosophy of perception.
  •  48
    Hatred: Understanding Our Most Dangerous Emotion
    Oxford University Press. 2020.
    Hatred: Understanding Our Most Dangerous Emotion The first in-depth philosophical analysis of personal hate and group hate, Hate: Understanding Our Most Dangerous Emotion explores how personal hatred can foster domestic violence and emotional abuse, how hate-proneness is a main contributor to the aggressive tendencies of borderlines, narcissists and psychopaths, how seemingly ordinary people embark on some of history's worst hate crimes, and how cohesive groups, subjected to spontaneous forces o…Read more
  •  48
    Seeing things
    Philosophical Perspectives 31 (1): 55-72. 2017.
  •  47
    Perceptual Appearances of Personality
    Philosophical Topics 44 (2): 83-103. 2016.
    Perceptual appearances of personality can be highly inaccurate, for example, when they rely on race, masculinity, and attractiveness, factors that have little to do with personality, as well as when they are the result of perceiver effects, such as an idiosyncratic tendency to view others negatively. This raises the question of whether these types of appearances can provide immediate justification for our judgments about personality. I argue that there are three reasons that we should think that…Read more
  •  42
    The Moral Psychology of Love (edited book)
    Rowman and Littlefield. 2022.
    This book will explore the moral dimensions of love from the standpoint of political philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience.
  •  36
    Parenting and the loss of autonomy
    The Philosophers' Magazine 72 31-32. 2016.
  •  35
    Mead's Temporal Realism
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35 (3). 1999.
  •  31
    This book collects original essays by top scholars that address questions about the nature, origins, and effects of ambivalence. While the nature of agency has received an enormous amount of attention, relatively little has been written about ambivalence or how it relates to topics such as agency, rationality, justification, knowledge, autonomy, self-governance, well-being, social cognition, and various other topics. Ambivalence presents unique questions related to many major philosophical debat…Read more
  •  30
    Presentist Four-Dimensionalism
    The Monist 83 (3): 341-356. 2000.
    Four-dimensionalism is the thesis that everyday objects, such as you and me, are space-time worms that persist through time by having temporal parts none of which is identical to the object itself. Objects are aggregates or sums of such temporal parts. The main virtue of four-dimensionalism is that it solves—or does away with—the problem of identity through change. The main charge raised against it is that it is inconsistent with the thesis according to which there is change in the world. If thi…Read more
  •  28
    Peirce on Abduction and Rational Control
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35 (1). 1999.
  •  26
    Knowability, possibility and paradox
    In Vincent Hendricks & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), New Waves in Epistemology, Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 270-299. 2007.
    The paradox of knowability threatens to draw a logical equivalence between the believable claim that all truths are knowable and the obviously false claim that all truths are known. In this paper we evaluate prominent proposals for resolving the paradox of knowability. For instance, we argue that Neil Tennant’s restriction strategy, which aims principally to restrict the main quantifier in ‘all truths are knowable’, does not get to the heart of the problem since there are knowability paradoxes t…Read more
  •  25
    I. Descriptions in Predicative Position The predicative analysis and Russell’s theory part company when it comes to the argument structure assigned to sentences like (1). (1) Washington is the greatest French soldier. On a standard Russellian analysis, (1) has the following (a) logical form and (b) truth conditions.
  •  24
    The moral status the human embryo
    Free Inquiry 23 (1): 45. 2002.
  •  23
    Deaf hearing: Implicit discrimination of auditory content in a patient with mixed hearing loss
    with Kristian Marlow, Morten Overgaard, Bennett L. Schwartz, Cengiz Zopluoglu, Steffie Tomson, Janina Neufed, Christopher Sinke, Christopher Owen, and David Eagleman
    Philosophical Psychology 30 (1-2): 21-43. 2017.
    We describe a patient LS, profoundly deaf in both ears from birth, with underdeveloped superior temporal gyri. Without hearing aids, LS displays no ability to detect sounds below a fixed threshold of 60 dBs, which classifies him as clinically deaf. Under these no-hearing-aid conditions, when presented with a forced-choice paradigm in which he is asked to consciously respond, he is unable to make above-chance judgments about the presence or location of sounds. However, he is able to make above-ch…Read more
  •  22
    Précis of Seeing and Saying
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 108 (2): 524-527. 2024.
  •  21
    In this book, Brit Brogaard defends the view that visual experience is like belief in having a representational content. Her defense differs from most previous defenses of this view in that it begins by looking at the language of ordinary speech. She provides a linguistic analysis of what we say when we say that things look a certain way or that the world appears to us to be a certain way. She then argues that this analysis can be used to argue for the view that visual experience has a represent…Read more
  •  21
    Replies to Alex Byrne, Mike Martin, and Nico Orlandi
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 108 (2): 556-581. 2024.
  •  21
    Gadflies, Coffeehouses and Citizen Philosophers
    The Philosophers' Magazine 80 80-87. 2018.
  •  15
    An Aristotelian approach to animal behavior
    Semiotica 127 (1-4): 199-214. 1999.
  •  14
    Can Virtue Reliabilism Explain the Value of Knowledge?
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (3): 335-354. 2006.
    I IntroductionA fundamental intuition about knowledge is that it is more valuable than mere true belief. This intuition is pervasive. We have an almost universal desire to know and nearly no desire to believe the truth accidentally. However, it turns out to be extremely difficult to explain why knowledge is more valuable. Linda Zagzebski and others have called this the ‘value problem.’ They argue that the value problem is particularly difficult to unravel for generic reliabilism. According to ge…Read more
  •  13
    Crazy About You
    The Philosophers' Magazine 70 (3rd Quarter): 66-71. 2015.
  •  12
    There is no abstract for this chapter, which introduces the reader to the papers in the book. The following is only a sample of the chapter: It is quite common for people not to be able to make up their minds. One of the most famous literary examples comes from Shakespeare’s play Hamlet, in which the protagonist Hamlet poses the well-known question “To be or not to be, that is the question,” while contemplating suicide. In the play, Hamlet is expressing discontent about life, as he thinks of the…Read more
  •  11
    Centered Worlds and the Content of Perception
    In Steven D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Wiley‐blackwell. 2011.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Abstract Relativistic Content The Argument from Primitive Colors The Argument from the Inverted Spectrum The Argument from Dual Looks The Argument from Duplication Conclusion References.