•  76
    The Anatomy of Aggression
    American Philosophical Quarterly 27 (3). 1990.
  •  48
    The Reliabilist Theory of Rational Belief
    The Monist 68 (2): 203-225. 1985.
    Niceties aside, Reliabilism is the claim that a belief is justified or rational if and only if it has a reliable source. One way to arrive at a belief is by inferring it from others through the application of a rule of inference. Hence Reliabilism has the consequence that a belief arrived at by applying a given rule of inference is rational if and only if arriving at that belief by applying the rule is reliable. This consequence of Reliabilism I will call the Reliabilist’s Thesis.
  •  12
    The Possibility of Knowledge: Nozick and His Critics (edited book)
    Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman and Littlefield. 1987.
    This volume of original essays assesses Nozick's analyses of knowledge and evidence and his approach to skepticism. Several of the contributors claim that Nozick has not succeeded in rebutting the skeptic; some offer fresh accounts of skepticism and its flaws; others criticize Nozick's externalist accounts of knowledge and evidence; still others welcome externalism but attempt to replace Nozick's accounts of knowledge and evidence with more plausible analyses.
  •  42
    Doxastic skepticism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (4): 529-538. 1987.
  •  18
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 102 (406): 360-362. 1993.
  •  60
    The knower, inside and out
    Synthese 74 (3): 349-67. 1988.
    Adherents of the epistemological position called internalism typically believe that the view they oppose, called externalism, is such a new and radical departure from the established way of seeing knowledge that its implications are uninteresting. Perhaps itis relatively novel, but the approach to knowledge with the greatest antiquity is the one that equates it withcertainty, and while this conception is amenable to the demands of the internalist, it is also a non-starter in the opinion of almos…Read more
  •  219
    The causal indicator analysis of knowledge
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (4): 563-587. 1987.
  •  311
    The epistemic predicament: Knowledge, Nozickian tracking, and scepticism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (1). 1984.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  200
    Annihilation
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (148): 233-252. 1987.
  •  148
    The absurdity of life
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1): 85-101. 1992.
  •  53
    The Easy Argument
    Acta Analytica 22 (4). 2007.
    Suppose Ted is in an ordinary house in good viewing conditions and believes red, his table is red, entirely because he sees his table and its color; he also believes not-white, it is false that his table is white and illuminated by a red light, because not-white is entailed by red. The following three claims about this table case clash, but each seems plausible: 1. Ted’s epistemic position is strong enough for him to know red. 2. Ted cannot know not-white on the basis of red. 3. The epistemic …Read more
  •  27
    Review of Bernard Schumacher, Death and Mortality in Contemporary Philosophy (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2011 (1). 2011.
  •  41
    Moore's Missing Principle
    Philosophical Papers 36 (1): 151-161. 2007.
    Philosophical Papers 36.1 (2007): 151-161.
  •  147
    Epistemic relativism
    Philosophical Issues 14 (1). 2004.
    Epistemic relativism rejects the idea that claims can be assessed from a universally applicable, objective standpoint. It is greatly disdained because it suggests that the real ‘basis’ for our views is something fleeting, such as ‘‘the techniques of mass persuasion’’ (Thomas Kuhn 1970) or the determination of intellectuals to achieve ‘‘solidarity’’ (Rorty 1984) or ‘‘keep the conversation going’’ (Rorty 1979). But epistemic relativism, like skepticism, is far easier to despise than to convincingl…Read more
  •  129
    Contrastivism and Skepticism
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 2 (1): 51-58. 2012.
    Recently, Jonathan Schaffer has defended a contrastivist analysis of knowledge. By appealing to his account, he has attempted to steer a path between skepticism and Moore-style antiskepticism: much like sensitivity theorists and contextualists, he offers significant concessions to, but ultimately rejects, both. In this essay I suggest that in fact Schaffer ends up succumbing to skepticism
  •  161
    The Philosophy of Death
    Cambridge University Press. 2009.
    The Philosophy of Death is a discussion of the basic philosophical issues concerning death, and a critical introduction to the relevant contemporary philosophical literature. Luper begins by addressing questions about those who die: What is it to be alive? What does it mean for you and me to exist? Under what conditions do we persist over time, and when do we perish? Next, he considers several questions concerning death, including: What does dying consist in; in particular, how does it differ fr…Read more
  •  183
    The Absurdity of Life
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 1-17. 1992.
  •  10
    To the death
    The Philosophers' Magazine 64 125-126. 2014.
  •  196
    The epistemic closure principle
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    Most of us think we can always enlarge our knowledge base by accepting things that are entailed by (or logically implied by) things we know. The set of things we know is closed under entailment (or under deduction or logical implication), which means that we know that a given claim is true upon recognizing, and accepting thereby, that it follows from what we know. However, some theorists deny that knowledge is closed under entailment, and the issue remains controversial. The arguments against cl…Read more
  •  90
    Restorative Rigging and the Safe Indication Account
    Synthese 153 (1): 161-170. 2006.
    Typical Gettieresque scenarios involve a subject, S, using a method, M, of believing something, p, where, normally, M is a reliable indicator of the truth of p, yet, in S’s circumstances, M is not reliable: M is deleteriously rigged. A different sort of scenario involves rigging that restores the reliability of a method M that is deleteriously rigged: M is restoratively rigged. Some theorists criticize the safe indication account of knowledge defended by Luper, Sosa, and Williamson on the ground…Read more
  •  35
    Persimals
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 52 (S1): 140-162. 2014.
    What sort of thing, fundamentally, are you and I? For convenience, I use the term persimal to refer to the kind of thing we are, whatever that kind turns out to be. Accordingly, the question is, what are persimals? One possible answer is that persimalhood consists in being a human animal, but many theorists, including Derek Parfit and Jeff McMahan, not to mention John Locke, reject this idea in favor of a radically different view, according to which persimalhood consists in having certain sorts …Read more
  •  29
    Giving your life meaning
    The Philosophers' Magazine 66 44-48. 2014.
  •  2
    Cartesian Skepticism
    In Duncan Pritchard & Sven Bernecker (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, Routledge. pp. 414--424. 2011.
  •  54
    The Skeptics: Contemporary Essays (edited book)
    Ashgate Publishing. 2003.
    Presented throughout in an accessible style, this book will prove particularly useful for students, researchers and general readers of philosophy who are ...
  •  29
    The AMA on Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide
    Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 59 (2): 189-197. 2016.
    The American Medical Association opposes physician-assisted suicide on the grounds that it “would ultimately cause more harm than good,” because it is “fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as healer,” and because it “would be difficult or impossible to control and would pose serious societal risks”. It condemns the practice of euthanasia as conducted by physicians for these reasons as well, and adds, by way of clarifying the serious risks at hand, that “euthanasia could readily b…Read more
  •  57
    Despite its plausibility, I mean to resist this argument. I will reject premise 1 on the grounds that dying may be atemporally bad for us. I will also reject premise 3. Some postmortem events are bad for some of us while we are alive. But I am not going to report some new exotic particle that makes backwards causation possible. As far as I know, 6 is true. If an event is responsible for a harm that we incur before the event itself occurs, it might be said to harm us retroactively ; if when or af…Read more
  •  32
    Living Up to Death
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 18 (4): 603-606. 2010.
    This Article does not have an abstract