•  6
    Review: Illusions about Uncertainty (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (3). 1985.
  •  33
    Gaifman
    Synthese 140 (1-2). 2004.
  •  8
    Making Choices (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 94 (11): 588-597. 1997.
  •  20
    ... But Fair to Chance
    Journal of Philosophy 70 (2): 52-55. 1973.
  •  251
    Pareto unanimity and consensus
    Journal of Philosophy 87 (9): 481-492. 1990.
  •  30
    Escape from Boredom: Edification According to Rorty
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (4). 1981.
    Richard Rorty sings in the antifoundationalist chorus. His song equates the rise of foundationalist epistemology with the professionalization of philosophy. The discordant notes he finds in the foundationalist score become, as a consequence, subversive of philosophy as an autonomous discipline.Nonetheless, the most salient feature of Rorty's recent book, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, is that it is by a professional philosopher, for professional philosophers and about the future of philoso…Read more
  •  44
    The wrong box
    Journal of Philosophy 80 (9): 534-542. 1983.
  •  18
    Perception as Input and as Reason for Action
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (sup1): 135-154. 1995.
  •  131
    Direct inference
    Journal of Philosophy 74 (1): 5-29. 1977.
  •  104
    The Demons of Decision
    The Monist 70 (2): 193-211. 1987.
    For three centuries, philosophers have mounted defenses against the melan genie with an obsessive intensity comparable to the Reaganite determination to squander American wealth on defenses against a Communist threat. And for three centuries, skeptics have argued for the futility of the expenditure of conceptual effort with no more success than critics of the Pentagon have had in stemming the flow of funds to the military and its industrial minions. My own sympathies are with the skeptics. Howev…Read more
  •  68
    Illusions about uncertainty (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (3): 331-340. 1985.
  •  107
    The Paradoxes of Allais and Ellsberg
    Economics and Philosophy 2 (1): 23. 1986.
    In The Enterprise of Knowledge, I proposed a general theory of rational choice which I intended as a characterization of a prescriptive theory of ideal rationality. A cardinal tenet of this theory is that assessments of expected value or expected utility in the Bayesian sense may not be representable by a numerical indicator or indeed induce an ordering of feasible options in a context of deliberation. My reasons for taking this position are related to my commitment to the inquiry-oriented appro…Read more
  •  289
    On indeterminate probabilities
    Journal of Philosophy 71 (13): 391-418. 1974.
  •  48
    Carol Rovane
    Synthese 140 (1-2). 2004.
  •  24
    Identity and conflict
    Social Research: An International Quarterly 74 (1): 25-50. 2007.
    A sketch of a way of characterizing multidimensional value commitments and the way they can come into conflict derived from my book Hard Choices is presented and applied to the question of how to characterize the relevance of identity to value commitments and conflict. The views of A.K. Sen and A. Bilgrami are examined in the light of these ideas
  • How Many Questions? (edited book)
    with L. S. Cauman, Charles D. Parsons, and Robert Schwartz
    Hacket. 1983.
  •  23
    Conjunctive bliss
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2): 254-255. 1983.
  •  99
    Money pumps and diachronic books
    Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2002 (3). 2002.
    The idea that rational agents should have acyclic preferences and should obey conditionalization has been defended on the grounds that otherwise an agent is threatened with becoming a “money pump.” This essay argues that such arguments fail to prove their claims
  •  64
    Commitment and change of view
    In José Luis Bermúdez & Alan Millar (eds.), Reason and Nature: Essays in the Theory of Rationality, Clarendon Press. pp. 209--232. 2002.
  • Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (3): 259-261. 1968.
  •  29
    Fallacy and controversy about base rates
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1): 31-32. 1996.
    Koehler's target article attempts a balanced view of the relevance of knowledge of base rates to judgments of subjective or credal probability, but he is not sensitive enough to the difference between requiring and permitting the equation of probability judgments with base rates, the interaction between precision of base rate and reference class information, and the possibility of indeterminate probability judgment.
  • Wayward naturalism : saving Dewey from himself
    In John R. Shook & Paul Kurtz (eds.), The future of naturalism, Humanity Books. 2009.
  •  204
    Kyburg on random designators
    Philosophy of Science 50 (4): 635-642. 1983.
    To ground judgments of credal probability on knowledge of chance via direct inference, one should appeal to the information about chances available relative to the most specific description known to be true of the trial event.Thus, to obtain a judgment of credal probability concerning the hypothesis that coin a landed heads at t given that it is known that at t it is known that a was tossed by Levi in 728 Philosophy Hall, the pertinent knowledge of chances concerns the chances of coin a landing …Read more
  •  150
    This paper seeks to defend the following conclusions: The program advanced by Carnap and other necessarians for probability logic has little to recommend it except for one important point. Credal probability judgments ought to be adapted to changes in evidence or states of full belief in a principled manner in conformity with the inquirer’s confirmational commitments—except when the inquirer has good reason to modify his or her confirmational commitment. Probability logic ought to spell out the …Read more
  •  38
    In “Truth and Probability” Ramsey claimed that the logic of consistency for probability is not a logic of truth. After supporting this claim, he proceeded to explore the possibilities for a logic of truth for probability. An examination of Ramsey's intent reveals that Ramsey was far from being an orthodox Bayesian when it comes to statistical reasoning. The relations between Ramsey's thought and the ideas of Keynes and Peirce are discussed