•  282
    In the past couple of decades, there were a few major attempts to establish the thesis of pragmatic infringement – that a significant pragmatic ingredient figures significantly in the truth-conditions for knowledge-ascriptions. As candidates, epistemic contextualism and Relativism flaunted conversational standards, and Stanley's SSI promoted stakes. These conceptions were propelled first and foremost by obviously pragmatic examples of knowledge ascriptions that seem to require a pragmatic compon…Read more
  •  2
  • The Paradox Of Surprise Examination
    Logique Et Analyse 21 (82): 337-344. 1978.
  •  94
    A probabilistic theory of knowledge
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (1). 2006.
    In this paper I provide a probabilistic account of factual knowledge,[1] based on the notion of chance.[2] This account has some affinity with my chance account of token causation,[3] but it neither relies on it nor presupposes it. Here I concentrate on the core cases of perceptual knowledge and of knowledge by memory (based on perception). The analysis of knowledge presented below is externalist; but pursuing such an analysis need not detract from the significance of attempts to flesh out justi…Read more
  •  68
    Quine and Modalities De Re
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (6): 295-328. 1982.
  •  282
    I argue that 'know' is only partly, though considerably, gradable. Its being only partly gradable is explained by its multi-parametrical character. That is, its truth-conditions involve different parameters, which are scalar in character, each of which is fully gradable. Robustness of knowledge may be higher or lower along different dimensions and different modes. This has little to do with whether 'know' is context-dependent, but it undermines Stanley's argument that the non-gradability of 'kno…Read more
  •  30
    Kripke’s Belief Puzzle
    Philosophy Research Archives 9 369-412. 1983.
    This article offers a resolution of Kripke’s well-known belief puzzle.
  •  62
    Beliefs and believing
    Theoria 52 (3): 129-45. 1986.
  •  63
    The Hesperus-Phosphorus case
    Theoria 50 (1): 1-35. 1984.
  •  34
    On Putnam's counterexample toa theory of counterfactuals
    Philosophical Papers 16 (3): 235-239. 1987.
    No abstract
  •  225
    Abstract In this paper I present a short outline of an Indicativity Theory of Knowledge, for the cases of Perceptual Knowledge and Knowledge by Memory. I explain the main rationale for a token-indicativity approach, and how it is fleshed out precisely in terms of chances. I elaborate on the account of the value of knowledge it provides, and what that value is. I explain why, given the rationale of conceiving Knowledge as token indicativity, separate sub-accounts in terms of chances should be…Read more
  •  46
    Overall Positive Causal Impact
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (2). 1994.
  •  50
    The problem facing us in this paper is that of how to analyze the notion of causal relevance. This is the inverse relation of causal dependence: A is causally irrelevant to C iff C is causally independent of A. As an example of causal relevance, consider: Example 1: A - The American astronaut on Mir scratched his left ear exactly an hour ago B - I am writing this paper right now. Intuitively, A was not causally relevant to B. It is this kind of intuition that I’ll mostly be relying on when analy…Read more
  •  14
    A Probabilistic Theory of Knowledge
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (1): 1-43. 2006.
    Hebrew University.
  •  128
    Seeing that and seeing as
    Noûs 27 (3): 279-302. 1993.
  •  11
    Kripke’s Belief Puzzle
    Philosophy Research Archives 9 369-412. 1983.
    This article offers a resolution of Kripke’s well-known belief puzzle.