•  103
    Literature, Life, and Modernity
    Cambridge University Press. 2008.
    In Literature, Life, and Modernity Richard Eldridge focuses on the question of a reader's or a viewer's response to a literary or dramatic work in a specific historical epoch ("modernity"). That is, in contrast with many other philosophical approaches to literature, he avoids fixing attention on any putative doctrinal (moral or political or diagnostic) claims in a literary work. Thereby, and in many other admirable ways, he avoids the danger of treating literature as philosophy manqué, concedes …Read more
  •  15
    Work on Oneself (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 62 (3): 666-668. 2009.
  •  104
    The Oxford handbook of philosophy and literature (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2009.
    The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Literature contains 23 newly commissioned essays by major philosophers and literary scholars that investigate literature ...
  •  13
    These challenging essays defend Romanticism against its critics. They argue that Romantic thought, interpreted as the pursuit of freedom in concrete contexts, remains a central and exemplary form of both artistic work and philosophical understanding. Marshalling a wide range of texts from literature, philosophy and criticism, Richard Eldridge traces the central themes and stylistic features of Romantic thinking in the work of Kant, Hölderlin, Wordsworth, Hardy, Wittgenstein, Cavell and Updike. T…Read more
  •  57
    Authority and estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge
    Philosophical Investigations 26 (4). 2003.
    Richard Moran, Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self Knowledge.
  •  63
    Certain metaphysical and epistemological presuppositions are shown to play a role in the defense of Davidson's claims that an empirically constructed theory of truth provides an adequate theory of meaning for any natural language. Dadivson puts forward demonstrative arguments in favor of these presuppositions in On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme, Thought and Talk, and The Method of Truth in Metaphysics. These arguments are examined and found to include controversial and dubitable assumptio…Read more
  •  32
    Frege (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 37 (3): 619-621. 1984.
    Recent revisionists about Frege have suggested that, contrary to Dummett's monumental work, Frege is to be understood as primarily an epistemologist, not a theorist of meaning. Currie's book is a valuable contribution to this new way of looking at Frege. Where Sluga, for example, focuses on the historical context of Frege's work and other writers are concerned with special topics such as naming and proof theory, Currie surveys the whole of Frege's career, highlighting his fundamental interest in…Read more
  •  4
    Richard Wollheim, Painting as an Art Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 8 (9): 374-378. 1988.
  •  23
    On Knowing How to Live: Coleridge's "Frost at Midnight"
    Philosophy and Literature 7 (2): 213-228. 1983.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Richard Eldridge ON KNOWING HOW TO LIVE: COLERIDGE'S "FROST AT MIDNIGHT" How ought human beings to live? It is both hard to ignore this question and hard to see how to go about answering it rationally. Moral philosophers have typically presented their works as deserving serious attention because they have supposed them to contain well-argued answers to this question. One very general way of describing the strategy of moral philosophe…Read more
  •  1
    Aesthetics and Ethics
    In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), The Oxford handbook of aesthetics, Oxford University Press. 2003.
  •  9
    The Thread of Life (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 39 (3): 590-592. 1986.
    When we imagine, previsage, and remember, do we engage in activities through which our selfhood or personhood is expressed, developed, and understood? In contemporary philosophy, the answer to this question has almost always been "No." Sometimes the self is taken to be a complex biological thing. Generally it is then added that this biological thing engages in certain so-called mental activities. But then how these activities are engaged in is either to be explained physically or modeled in a co…Read more
  •  4
    Poetic Justice (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 94 (8): 431-434. 1997.
  •  37
    BY THE middle of the nineteenth century, serious difficulties in carrying out the Cartesian project of explaining through attention to our ideas how we may know things as they really are had become evident. A satisfactory account of the connection between occurrences of ideas in us and the properties of things apart from our ideas of them, an account promised by Descartes in the Meditations, had not been forthcoming. Descartes' claim that God's omnipotence guarantees that the members of some rec…Read more
  •  15
  •  3
    Richard Wollheim, Painting as an Art (review)
    Philosophy in Review 8 374-378. 1988.
  •  15
  •  24
    Cavell and the American Jeremiad
    Journal of Philosophical Research 39 377-391. 2014.
    Building on remarks by Dewey, Brandom, and Wittgenstein among others, this paper characterizes and defends a general style of philosophy as elucidatory analysis of concepts in circulation within a culture. The presence of this general style is then traced briefly in Quine and Beardsley. I then raise the question whether there is anything distinctively American about this general style. Drawing on work by Sacvan Bercovitch, I argue that use of this style is motivated by America’s distinctive reli…Read more
  •  38
    Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 37 (4): 859-861. 1984.
    Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language is very much a work on Wittgenstein's epistemology, not on his philosophy of mind. Kripke focuses on Wittgenstein's account, principally set out in sections 1-242 of Philosophical Investigations, of our grasp of concepts and our ability to apply them; he discusses Wittgenstein's views about such topics as imagination, sensations, and consciousness only in passing as they bear on the former topic.
  •  50
    How Movies Think: Cavell on Film as a Medium of Art
    Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 51 (1): 3-20. 2014.
    Stanley Cavell’s writing about movies, from the more theoretical and general The World Viewed (1971) to the later works on specific genres (Pursuits of Happiness, Contesting Tears), has a unifying theme: some movies as (successful) art investigate conditions of accomplished selfhood and interest in experience in medium-specific ways. This claim is explained and defended by explicating the details of the medium-specificity of the moving photographic image (and its history of uses) and by focusing…Read more
  •  28
    Stanley Cavell (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2003.
    Contemporary Philosophy in Focus offers a series of introductory volumes on many of the dominant philosophical thinkers of the current age. Stanley Cavell has been one of the most creative and independent of contemporary philosophical voices. At the core of his thought is the view that skepticism is not a theoretical position to be refuted by philosophical theory but is a reflection of the fundamental limits of human knowledge of the self, of others and of the external world that must be accepte…Read more
  •  57
    Problems and prospects of Wittgensteinian aesthetics
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 45 (3): 251-261. 1987.