•  12
    Dialectical Materialism
    Irish Philosophical Journal 1 (1): 53-69. 1984.
  • Shorter Reviews
    Radical Philosophy 41 35. 1985.
  •  33
    Should Nationalists be Communitarians?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 13 (2): 215-220. 1996.
    John O'Neill argues in a recent article, ‘Should Communitarians be Nationalists?’, that communitarians are wrong to be committed to the defence of ties of nationhood, both because the nation‐state's rise is associated with the disappearance of the ties of community and because the nation is an illusory community. I argue that the evidence that communitarianism is committed as charged to the defence of nationality is unconvincing. Further, the familiar accusation that the nation is a false or unr…Read more
  •  83
    Inequality Re-examined
    Philosophical Quarterly 45 (181): 553. 1995.
    This book develops some of the most important themes of Sen's works over the last decade. He argues in a rich and subtle approach that we should be concerned with people's capabilities rather than their resources or welfare
  •  5
    A Brief Tribute to Stephen Mills
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 9 (4): 499-500. 2001.
  • News
    Radical Philosophy 41 43. 1985.
  •  59
    Sex for sale
    Cogito 3 (1): 47-51. 1989.
  •  25
    Membership and Justice
    Theoria 49 (99): 7-25. 2002.
  •  202
    Children, multiculturalism and education
    In David Archard & Colin M. Macleod (eds.), The Moral and Political Status of Children, Oxford University Press. pp. 150--158. 2002.
    There are three possible justifications of the claim cultural communities make for their right to transmit an identity to their children. A group strategy and a parenting strategy are both defective. More promising is the view that there is value to children in the sharing of a familial life. But parental authority is limited by the requirement that children acquire sufficient autonomy. Some multicultural policies are thus not ruled out by the recognition of the need to accommodate children's in…Read more
  • Ross Harrison, Democracy
    Radical Philosophy. forthcoming.
  •  33
    Apply within
    The Philosophers' Magazine 39 (39): 50-52. 2007.
  •  1
    Gordon Graham, The Internet: A Philosophical Inquiry (review)
    Ends and Means 4 (3). 2000.
  •  174
    Liberalism and Prostitution * By PETER DE MARNEFFE
    Analysis 70 (3): 595-597. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  41
    Child Abuse: parental rights and the interests of the child
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 7 (2): 183-194. 1990.
    I criticise the ‘liberal’view of the proper relationship between the family and State, namely that, although the interests of the child should be paramount, parents are entitled to rights of both privacy and autonomy which should be abrogated only when the child suffers a specifiable harm. I argue that the right to bear children is not absolute, and that it only grounds a right to rear upon an objectionable proprietarian picture of the child as owned by its producer. If natural parents have any …Read more
  •  94
    Political disagreement, legitimacy, and civility
    Philosophical Explorations 4 (3). 2001.
    For many contemporary liberal political philosophers the appropriate response to the facts of pluralism is the requirement of public reasonableness, namely that individuals should be able to offer to their fellow citizens reasons for their political actions that can generally be accepted.This article finds wanting two possible arguments for such a requirement: one from a liberal principle of legitimacy and the other from a natural duty of political civility. A respect in which conversational res…Read more
  •  19
    Three ways to be a good patriot
    Public Affairs Quarterly 9 (2): 101-113. 1995.
  •  40
    Freedom not to be free
    Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161): 453. 1990.
  • JJ Clarke, Oriental Enlightenment
    Radical Philosophy. forthcoming.
  •  1
    Apply within
    The Philosophers' Magazine 39 50-52. 2007.
  •  252
    Procreation and Parenthood offers new and original essays by leading philosophers on some of the main ethical issues raised by these activities.
  •  113
    Exploited consent
    Journal of Social Philosophy 25 (3): 92--101. 1994.
    The article considers whether a professional's sexual relations with a client are wrong, even if the client's consent is not coerced, incapacitated or manipulated, the impartial conduct of professional affairs is not interfered with, and there are no damaged third parties. It argues that consent may be ``exploited'' if it is forthcoming only due to the occupancy of respective positions within an unequal relationship whose scope excludes such intimacy. The article explains the use of the term, ex…Read more
  •  120
    Selling yourself: Titmuss's argument against a market in blood (review)
    The Journal of Ethics 6 (1): 87-102. 2002.
    This article defends Richard Titmuss''s argument, and PeterSinger''s sympathetic support for it, against orthodoxphilosophical criticism. The article specifies thesense in which a market in blood is ``dehumanising'''' ashaving to do with a loss of ``imagined community'''' orsocial ``integration'''', and not with a loss of valued or``deeper'''' liberty. It separates two ``domino arguments''''– the ``contamination of meaning'''' argument and the``erosion of motivation'''' argument which support, i…Read more
  •  7
    Political philosophy
    Philosophical Books 46 (2): 178-182. 2005.
  •  8
    No Title available: Reviews
    Economics and Philosophy 14 (2): 362-368. 1998.