•  74
    Does the Argument from Evil Assume a Consequentialist Morality?
    Faith and Philosophy 17 (3): 306-319. 2000.
    In this paper, I argue that the some of the most popular and influential formulations of the Argument from Evil (AE) assume a moral perspective that is essentially consequentialist, and would therefore be unacceptable to deontologists. Specifically, I examine formulations of the argument offered by William Rowe and Bruce Russell, both of whom explicitly assert that their formulation of AE is theoretically neutral with respect to consequentialism, and can be read in a way that is unobjectionable …Read more
  •  160
    One reason for the persistent appeal of Don Marquis' ‘future like ours’ argument is that it seems to offer a way to approach the debate about the morality of abortion while sidestepping the difficult task of establishing whether the fetus is a person. This essay argues that in order to satisfactorily address both of the chief objections to FLO – the ‘identity objection’ and the ‘contraception objection’ – Marquis must take a controversial stand on what is most essential to being the kind of enti…Read more
  •  67
    The Moral Justification of Violence
    Social Theory and Practice 28 (3): 445-464. 2002.
  • On William A. Wallace, O.P., The Modeling of Nature
    with Benedict Ashley
    The Thomist 61 625-640. 1997.
  •  48
    Rape as an Essentially Contested Concept
    Hypatia 16 (2): 43-66. 2001.
    Because “rape” has such a powerful appraisive meaning, how one defines the term has normative significance. Those who define rape rigidly so as to exclude contemporary feminist understandings are therefore seeking to silence some moral perspectives “by definition.” I argue that understanding rape as an essentially contested concept allows the concept sufficient flexibility to permit open moral discourse, while at the same time preserving a core meaning that can frame the discourse.
  •  51
    Punishment and Community: The Reintegrative Theory of Punishment
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (1). 1996.
    There seems to be nearly universal agreement that society cannot do without some form of criminal punishment. At the same time, it is generally acknowledged that punishment, involving as it does the imposition of hardship and suffering, stands in need of justification. What form such a justification should take, however, is a matter of considerable contention, in part because of basic theoretical disagreements on the nature of moral obligation, and in part because of disagreements concerning the…Read more
  •  51
    Deep ecology and the irrelevance of morality
    Environmental Ethics 18 (4): 411-424. 1996.
    Both Arne Naess and Warwick Fox have argued that deep ecology, in terms of “Selfrealization,” is essentially nonmoral. I argue that the attainment of the ecological Self does not render morality in the richest sense “superfluous,” as Fox suggests. To the contrary, the achievement of the ecological Self is a precondition for being a truly moral person, both from the perspective of a robust Kantian moral frameworkand from the perspective of Aristotelian virtue ethics. The opposition between selfre…Read more
  •  95
    Richard Swinburne’s formulation of the argument from evil is representative of a pervasive way of understanding the challenge evil poses for theistic belief. But there is an error in Swinburne’s formulation : he fails to consider possible deontological constraints on God’s legitimate responses to evil. To demonstrate the error’s significance, I show that some important objections to Swinburne’s theodicy admit of a novel answer once we correct for Swinburne’s Lapse. While more is needed to show t…Read more
  •  4
    Responses
    Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 6 (1): 165-187. 2003.
  •  123
    Defining Terrorism for Public Policy Purposes: The Group-Target Definition
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (2): 253-278. 2010.
    For the sake of developing and evaluating public policy decisions aimed at combating terrorism, we need a precise public definition of terrorism that distinguishes terrorism from other forms of violence. Ordinary usage does not provide a basis for such a definition, and so it must be stipulative. I propose essentially pragmatic criteria for developing such a stipulative public definition. After noting that definitions previously proposed in the philosophical literature are inadequate based on th…Read more
  •  10
    Responses
    with Gregory J. Coulter, Laura L. Garcia, and Peter Shea
    Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 6 (1): 165-187. 2003.
  •  38
    Response: Personal Pacifism, Another Look
    The Acorn 11 (1): 62-62. 2000.
  •  12
    Deep Ecology and the Irrelevance of Morality
    Environmental Ethics 18 (4): 411-424. 1996.
    Both Arne Naess and Warwick Fox have argued that deep ecology, in terms of “Selfrealization,” is essentially nonmoral. I argue that the attainment of the ecological Self does not render morality in the richest sense “superfluous,” as Fox suggests. To the contrary, the achievement of the ecological Self is a precondition for being a truly moral person, both from the perspective of a robust Kantian moral frameworkand from the perspective of Aristotelian virtue ethics. The opposition between selfre…Read more
  •  1
  • Review (review)
    The Thomist 57 690-694. 1993.
  •  22
    When philosophers contribute to public debates as polarized as contemporary ones about theistic belief, it is common to encounter responses that, philosophically, are woefully misguided. While it is tempting to simply dismiss them, a closer examination of recurring responses can offer insight of philosophical significance. In this paper I exemplify the value of engaging with recurring but misguided popular objections by looking carefully at one such objection to my recent book, Is God a Delusion…Read more
  •  6
    7. Christianity and Partisan Politics
    Logos. Anales Del Seminario de Metafísica [Universidad Complutense de Madrid, España] 2 (4). 1999.
  •  54
    Universalism and autonomy: Towards a comparative defense of universalism
    Faith and Philosophy 18 (2): 222-240. 2001.
    In arecent article, Michael Murray critiques several versions of universalism-that is, the doctrine that in the end all persons are saved. Of particular interest to Murray is Thomas Talbott’s version of universalism (called SU1 by Murray), which puts forward a strategy for ensuring universal salvation that purports to preserve the autonomy of the creatures saved. Murray argues that, on the contrary, the approach put forward in SU1 is not autonomy-preserving at all. I argue that this approach pre…Read more
  •  86
  •  41
    Self-Defense and the Principle of Generic Consistency
    Social Theory and Practice 32 (3): 415-438. 2006.
  •  39
    Efforts to protect endangered species by regulating the use of privately owned lands are routinely resisted by appeal to the private property rights of landowners. Recently, the 'wise-use' movement has emerged as a primary representative of these landowners' claims. In addressing the issues raised by the wise-use movement and others like them, legal scholars and philosophers have typically examined the scope of private property rights and the extent to which these rights should influence public …Read more