University of Oxford
Faculty of Philosophy
DPhil, 1978
St Andrews, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
Areas of Interest
Medieval Logic
  •  7
    Questiones libri Porphirii (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 69 (2): 400-401. 2015.
  • Homophone Semantik für die relevante Aussagenlogik
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 23 (59): 77-89. 1989.
  •  138
    Hairier than Putnam Thought
    with Crispin Wright
    Analysis 45 (1). 1985.
    " In 'Vagueness and Alternative Logic' (Realism and Reason, Cambridge 1983, pp. 271-86, especially 285-6), Hilary Putnam puts forward a suggestion for a formal treatment of the logic of vagueness. … Putnam admits that, at the time of writing, he had not thought this idea through. What will already be apparent to the alert reader is that, in order to disclose serious difficulties for the proposal, Putnam would not have had to think far."
  •  89
    Harmonic inferentialism and the logic of identity
    Review of Symbolic Logic 9 (2): 408-420. 2016.
    Inferentialism claims that the rules for the use of an expression express its meaning without any need to invoke meanings or denotations for them. Logical inferentialism endorses inferentialism specically for the logical constants. Harmonic inferentialism, as the term is introduced here, usually but not necessarily a subbranch of logical inferentialism, follows Gentzen in proposing that it is the introduction-rules whch give expressions their meaning and the elimination-rules should accord harmo…Read more
  • Conditionals and the Ramsey Test
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 69 47-64. 1995.
    Much thinking about conditionals over the last twenty years has been stimulated by the so-called 'Ramsey test'. Ramsey's idea was simple, but appealing. One should believe a conditional, 'if A then B' if one would come to believe B if one were to add A to one's stock of beliefs. The Ramsey test does not justify treating conditionals with true antecedent and consequent as true, and accepting it does not require one to accept either the similarity or probability theories of the conditional. It cer…Read more
  •  16
    Preface
    Philosophia Scientiae 15 1-5. 2011.
    This volume would not exist without the help of all those who contributed to the organisation of the MacColl centenary meeting (Boulogne-sur-Mer, 9--10 October 2009). We are especially grateful to Bruno Béthouart, Jacques Dubucs, Gerhard Heinzmann, and Shahid Rahman. We would also like to thank Michael Astroh, Sandrine Avril, Anny Bégard, Christian Berner, Pierre-Édouard Bour, Peggy Cardon, Emmanuelle Jablonsky, Christian Mac Coll, Tony Mann, Gildas Nzokou, Max Papyle, Bernard Quéh...
  •  1
    A. Broadie, "The Circle of John Mair" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (46): 120. 1987.
  •  10
    The Philosophy of Thomas Reid: A Collection of Essays (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2003.
    Thomas Reid was one of the greatest philosophers of the eighteenth century and a contemporary of Kant's. This volume is part of a new wave of international interest in Reid from a new generation of scholars. The volume opens with an introduction to Reid's life and work, including biographical material previously little known. A classic essay by Reid himself - 'Of Power' - is then reproduced, in which he sets out his distinctive account of causality and agency. This is followed by ten original es…Read more
  •  56
    Proof-theoretic validity
    In Colin R. Caret & Ole T. Hjortland (eds.), Foundations of Logical Consequence, Oxford University Press. pp. 136-158. 2015.
    The idea of proof-theoretic validity originated in the work of Gentzen, when he suggested that the meaning of each logical expression was encapsulated in its introduction-rules. The idea was developed by Prawitz and Dummett, but came under attack by Prior under the soubriquet 'analytic validity'. Logical truths and logical consequences are deemed analytically valid by virtue of following, in a way which the present chapter clarifies, from the meaning of the logical constants. But different logic…Read more
  •  89
    Intentionality: Meinongianism and the medievals
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (3). 2004.
    Intentional verbs create three different problems: problems of non-existence, of indeterminacy, and of failure of substitutivity. Meinongians tackle the first problem by recognizing non-existent objects; so too did many medieval logicians. Meinongians and the medievals approach the problem of indeterminacy differently, the former diagnosing an ellipsis for a propositional complement, the latter applying their theory directly to non-propositional complements. The evidence seems to favour the Mein…Read more
  •  61
    Logical consequence as truth-preservation
    Logique and Analyse 183 (4): 479-493. 2003.
    t is often suggested that truth-preservation is insufficient for logical consequence, and that consequence needs to satisfy a further condition of relevance. Premises and conclusion in a valid consequence must be relevant to one another, and truth-preservation is too coarse-grained a notion to guarantee that. Thus logical consequence is the intersection of truth-preservation and relevance. This situation has the absurd consequence that one might concede that the conclusion of an arg…Read more
  •  1
    Truth, Signification and Paradox
    In T. Achourioti, H. Galinon, J. Martínez Fernández & K. Fujimoto (eds.), Unifying the Philosophy of Truth, Imprint: Springer. pp. 393-408. 2015.
    Thomas Bradwardine's solution to the semantic paradoxes, presented in his Insolubilia written in Oxford in the early 1320s, turns on two main principles: that a proposition is true only if things are wholly as it signifies; and that signification is closed under consequence. After exploring the background in Walter Burley's account of the signification of propositions, the question is considered of the extent to which Bradwardine's theory is compatible with the distribution of truth over conjunc…Read more
  •  7
  •  105
    Hypertasks
    with Peter Clark
    Synthese 61 (3). 1984.
  •  304
    General-Elimination Harmony and the Meaning of the Logical Constants
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (5): 557-576. 2010.
    Inferentialism claims that expressions are meaningful by virtue of rules governing their use. In particular, logical expressions are autonomous if given meaning by their introduction-rules, rules specifying the grounds for assertion of propositions containing them. If the elimination-rules do no more, and no less, than is justified by the introduction-rules, the rules satisfy what Prawitz, following Lorenzen, called an inversion principle. This connection between rules leads to a general form of…Read more
  •  19
    This book presents the very latest research on the medieval use of sophisms in logical and grammatical investigation by twenty-three of the leading experts in Europe and beyond. Important insights into the genre of sophismatic treatises have been gained only very recently, and the organisation of the European Symposium on this topic in 1990 led to a concentration of research and evaluation of insights. The papers are divided into three groups: one covers textual study and analysis of the role of…Read more
  •  30
    Miller, Bradwardine and the Truth
    Discusiones Filosóficas 12 (18): 229-35. 2011.
    In his article "Verdades antiguas y modernas" (in the same issue, pp. 207-27), David Miller criticised Thomas Bradwardine’s theory of truth and signification and my defence of Bradwardine’s application of it to the semantic paradoxes. Much of Miller’s criticism is sympathetic and helpful in gaining a better understanding of the relationship between Bradwardine’s proposed solution to the paradoxes and Alfred Tarski’s. But some of Miller’s criticisms betray a misunderstanding of crucial aspects of…Read more
  •  57
    Conditionals and the Ramsey Test
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 69 (1). 1995.
  •  97
    Plural signification and the Liar paradox
    Philosophical Studies 145 (3): 363-375. 2009.
    In recent years, speech-act theory has mooted the possibility that one utterance can signify a number of different things. This pluralist conception of signification lies at the heart of Thomas Bradwardine’s solution to the insolubles, logical puzzles such as the semantic paradoxes, presented in Oxford in the early 1320s. His leading assumption was that signification is closed under consequence, that is, that a proposition signifies everything which follows from what it signifies. Then any propo…Read more
  •  6
    Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons (review)
    Mind 124 (496): 1353-1356. 2015.
  •  47
    A survey of the life of Hugh MacColl (1837-1909)
    with Michael Astroh and Ivor Grattan-Guinness
    History and Philosophy of Logic 22 (2): 81-98. 2001.
    The Scottish logician Hugh MacColl is well known for his innovative contributions to modal and nonclassical logics. However, until now little biographical information has been available about his academic and cultural background, his personal and professional situation, and his position in the scientific community of the Victorian era. The present article reports on a number of recent findings
  •  33
  •  126
    Identity and harmony
    Analysis 64 (2). 2004.
  •  315
    Truthmakers and the disjunction thesis
    Mind 109 (432): 67-80. 2000.
    The correspondence theory of truth has experienced something of a revival recently in the form of the Truthmaker Axiom: whatever is true, something makes it true. We consider various postulates which have been proposed to characterize truthmaking, in particular, the Disjunction Thesis (DT), that whatever makes a disjunction true must make one or other disjunct true. In conjunction with certain other assumptions, DT leads to triviality. We show that there are elaborations of truthmaking on which …Read more
  •  7
    Book Reviews (review)
    with Rezensiert von H. Berger, E. J. Ashworth, J. W. Van Evra, I. Grattan-Guinness, W. Veldman, Kenneth G. Ferguson, Barry Smith, H. A. Lewis, Michele Malatesta, Bob Hale, and Tomis Kapitan
    History and Philosophy of Logic 12 (2): 241-267. 1991.
    MEDIEVAL LOGICCARLOS A. DUFOUR, Die Lehre der Proprietates Terminorum. Sinn und Referenz in mittelalterlicher Logik. München, Hamden, Wien: Philosophia, 1989. 312 pp. 148 DM.NORMAN KRETZMANN and BARBARA ENSIGN KRETZMANN The Sophismata of Richard Kilvington. Oxford: Published for the British Academy by Oxford University Press, 1990. xx + 156 pp. £27.50.LOGIC AND MATHEMATICSSOULEYMANE BACHIR DIAGNE, Boole. Paris: Editions Belin, 1989. 262pp. 75 Ffr.M.-M. TOEPELL, Über die Entstehung von David Hilb…Read more