University of Oxford
Faculty of Philosophy
DPhil, 1978
St Andrews, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
Areas of Interest
Medieval Logic
  •  7
    Questiones libri Porphirii (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 69 (2): 400-401. 2015.
  • Homophone Semantik für die relevante Aussagenlogik
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 23 (59): 77-89. 1989.
  •  139
    Hairier than Putnam Thought
    with Crispin Wright
    Analysis 45 (1). 1985.
    " In 'Vagueness and Alternative Logic' (Realism and Reason, Cambridge 1983, pp. 271-86, especially 285-6), Hilary Putnam puts forward a suggestion for a formal treatment of the logic of vagueness. … Putnam admits that, at the time of writing, he had not thought this idea through. What will already be apparent to the alert reader is that, in order to disclose serious difficulties for the proposal, Putnam would not have had to think far."
  •  89
    Harmonic inferentialism and the logic of identity
    Review of Symbolic Logic 9 (2): 408-420. 2016.
    Inferentialism claims that the rules for the use of an expression express its meaning without any need to invoke meanings or denotations for them. Logical inferentialism endorses inferentialism specically for the logical constants. Harmonic inferentialism, as the term is introduced here, usually but not necessarily a subbranch of logical inferentialism, follows Gentzen in proposing that it is the introduction-rules whch give expressions their meaning and the elimination-rules should accord harmo…Read more
  • Conditionals and the Ramsey Test
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 69 47-64. 1995.
    Much thinking about conditionals over the last twenty years has been stimulated by the so-called 'Ramsey test'. Ramsey's idea was simple, but appealing. One should believe a conditional, 'if A then B' if one would come to believe B if one were to add A to one's stock of beliefs. The Ramsey test does not justify treating conditionals with true antecedent and consequent as true, and accepting it does not require one to accept either the similarity or probability theories of the conditional. It cer…Read more
  •  20
    Preface
    Philosophia Scientiae 15 1-5. 2011.
    This volume would not exist without the help of all those who contributed to the organisation of the MacColl centenary meeting (Boulogne-sur-Mer, 9--10 October 2009). We are especially grateful to Bruno Béthouart, Jacques Dubucs, Gerhard Heinzmann, and Shahid Rahman. We would also like to thank Michael Astroh, Sandrine Avril, Anny Bégard, Christian Berner, Pierre-Édouard Bour, Peggy Cardon, Emmanuelle Jablonsky, Christian Mac Coll, Tony Mann, Gildas Nzokou, Max Papyle, Bernard Quéh...
  •  1
    A. Broadie, "The Circle of John Mair" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (46): 120. 1987.
  •  11
    The Philosophy of Thomas Reid: A Collection of Essays (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2003.
    Thomas Reid was one of the greatest philosophers of the eighteenth century and a contemporary of Kant's. This volume is part of a new wave of international interest in Reid from a new generation of scholars. The volume opens with an introduction to Reid's life and work, including biographical material previously little known. A classic essay by Reid himself - 'Of Power' - is then reproduced, in which he sets out his distinctive account of causality and agency. This is followed by ten original es…Read more
  •  57
    Proof-theoretic validity
    In Colin R. Caret & Ole T. Hjortland (eds.), Foundations of Logical Consequence, Oxford University Press. pp. 136-158. 2015.
    The idea of proof-theoretic validity originated in the work of Gentzen, when he suggested that the meaning of each logical expression was encapsulated in its introduction-rules. The idea was developed by Prawitz and Dummett, but came under attack by Prior under the soubriquet 'analytic validity'. Logical truths and logical consequences are deemed analytically valid by virtue of following, in a way which the present chapter clarifies, from the meaning of the logical constants. But different logic…Read more
  •  1414
    Merely Confused Supposition
    Franciscan Studies 40 (1): 265-97. 1980.
    In this article, we discuss the notion of merely confused supposition as it arose in the medieval theory of suppositio personalis. The context of our analysis is our formalization of William of Ockham's theory of supposition sketched in Mind 86 (1977), 109-13. The present paper is, however, self-contained, although we assume a basic acquaintance with supposition theory. The detailed aims of the paper are: to look at the tasks that supposition theory took on itself and to use our formalization to…Read more
  •  28
    Concepts and Meaning in Medieval Philosophy
    Philosophy and Theology 8 1-20. 1999.
    In his recent study, Concepts, Fodor identifies five nonnegotiable constraints on any theory of concepts. These theses were all shared by the standard medieval theories of concepts. However, those theories were cognitivist, in contrast with Fodor’s: concepts are definitions, a form of natural knowledge. The medieval theories were formed under two influences, from Aristotle by way of Boethius, and from Augustine. The tension between them resulted in the Ockhamist notion of a natural language, con…Read more
  •  29
    Paradoxes of Signification
    New Content is Available for Vivarium. 2018.
    _ Source: _Page Count 21 Ian Rumfitt has recently drawn our attention to a couple of paradoxes of signification, claiming that although Thomas Bradwardine’s “multiple-meanings” account of truth and signification can solve the first of them, it cannot solve the second. The paradoxes of signification were in fact much discussed by Bradwardine’s successors in the fourteenth century. Bradwardine’s solution appears to turn on a distinction between the principal and the consequential signification of …Read more
  •  77
    How Is Material Supposition Possible?
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 8 (1): 1-20. 1999.
    I. SUPPOSITION AND SIGNIFICATIONIn an insightful article on the medieval theory of supposition, Elizabeth Karger noted a remarkable development in the characterization of the material mode of supposition between William of Ockham and his contemporaries in the early fourteenth century and Paul of Venice and others at the turn of the fifteenth century.1. E. Karger, “La Supposition Materielle comme Supposition Significative: Paul de Venise, Paul de Pergula,” in A. Maierú, ed., English Logic in Ital…Read more
  •  1
    Marilyn McCord Adams, "William Ockham"
    Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161): 537. 1990.
  • HUGHES, G. E.: "John Buridan on Self-Reference" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (n/a): 423. 1984.
  •  23
    Johannes Buridanus: Summulae de Practica Sophismatum (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 45 (1): 157-158. 2007.
    Stephen Read - Johannes Buridanus: Summulae de Practica Sophismatum - Journal of the History of Philosophy 45:1 Journal of the History of Philosophy 45.1 157-158 Muse Search Journals This Journal Contents Reviewed by Stephen Read University of St. Andrews Fabienne Pironet, editor. Johannes Buridanus: Summulae de Practica Sophismatum. Artistarium 10–9. Turnhout: Brepols 2004. Pp. xlix + 193. Paper, €40.00. John Buridan was an unusual figure in fourteenth-century logic and philosophy. Logic was at …Read more
  •  5
    Book reviews (review)
    with C. Hill, Bertil Rolf, Gregory Landini, Timothy Williamson, Desmond Paul Henry, I. Grattan-Guinness, Simone Martini, Reinhard Hülsen, R. N. Bosley, Claire Ortiz Hill, J. Hund, Kenneth G. Ferguson, Maía Frápolli, F. Widebäck, Peter øhrstrøm, and Nino B. Cocchiarella
    History and Philosophy of Logic 17 (1-2): 85-119. 1996.
    A. Kenny, Frege, an introduction to the founder of modern analytic philosophy. London:Penguin, 1995. viii-h223pp. £7.99 T. Willamson, Vagueness. London:Routledge, 1994. xiii-f-325 pp. £35.00 TOM BU...
  •  159
    Harmony and autonomy in classical logic
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (2): 123-154. 2000.
    Michael Dummett and Dag Prawitz have argued that a constructivist theory of meaning depends on explicating the meaning of logical constants in terms of the theory of valid inference, imposing a constraint of harmony on acceptable connectives. They argue further that classical logic, in particular, classical negation, breaks these constraints, so that classical negation, if a cogent notion at all, has a meaning going beyond what can be exhibited in its inferential use. I argue that Dummett gives …Read more
  •  46
    Saving Truth from Paradox, by Hartry Field
    Mind 119 (473): 215-219. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  16
    A survey of the life of Hugh MacColl (1837-1909)
    with Michael Astroh and Ivor Grattan-Guinness
    Philosophia Scientiae 15 7-29. 2011.
    Introduction Contrary to a widespread assumption the modern history of modal logic did not start with C. I. Lewis’ Survey of Symbolic Logic [Lewis 1918]. His eminent work was preceded by some 20 years by H. MacColl’s fifth article on ‘The Calculus of Equivalent Statements’. This article was read at the London Mathematical Society on 12 November 1896. Some months later it was published in the Society’s Proceedings [MacColl 1896-1897]. During the following years MacColl presented his logic prim...
  •  13
    Epistemic Logic in the Later Middle Ages
    Philosophical Books 36 (2): 102-104. 1995.
  •  66
    Richard Kilvington and the Theory of Obligations
    Vivarium 53 (2-4): 391-404. 2015.
    Kretzmann and Spade were led by Richard Kilvington’s proposed revisions to the rules of obligations in his discussion of the 47th sophism in his Sophismata to claim that the purpose of obligational disputations was the same as that of counterfactual reasoning. Angel d’Ors challenged this interpretation, realising that the reason for Kilvington’s revision was precisely that he found the art of obligation unsuited to the kind of reasoning which lay at the heart of the sophismatic argument. In his …Read more
  •  65
    Necessary truth and proof
    Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 51 (121): 47-67. 2010.
    What makes necessary truths true? I argue that all truth supervenes on how things are, and that necessary truths are no exception. What makes them true are proofs. But if so, the notion of proof needs to be generalized to include verification-transcendent proofs, proofs whose correctness exceeds our ability to verify it. It is incumbent on me, therefore, to show that arguments, such as Dummett's, that verification- truth is not compatible with the theory of meaning, are mistaken. The answer is t…Read more